Beyond the first three subgroups of problems, C extends the complexity of the "combination problem' as follows:
". . . There are a few other aspects of the combination problem, corresponding to different aspects of macroexperience that need explaining. There is the unity problem: how do microexperiences come together to yield a unified consciousness? There is the boundary problem (Rosenberg 1998): how do microexperiences come together to yield a bounded consciousness? There is the awareness problem: how do microexperiences come together to yield awareness of qualities? And there is the grain problem (Maxwell 1979; Lockwood 1993): how do microexperiences come together 2Dainton (2011) calls this problem the “derivation problem”. 5 to yield homogeneous macroexperiences, such as a homogeneous experience of red, instead of an enormous jagged array of distinct qualities? Some of these problems might be assimilated to earlier problems (the first three plausibly involve aspects of subjective character, the last involves an aspect of qualitative character, and all involve aspects of structure), but it is useful to have them on the table explicitly.
It is common for a proposed solution to the combination problem to address only one of these problems: most often the subject combination problem and occasionally the quality combination problem. It should be stressed that a satisfactory solution to the combination problem must address all of these problems. This raises the bar for a solution, as it is far from clear that any single proposal can solve all the problems at once. One might appeal to separate proposals for solving the problems one at a time, but then it is far from clear that these proposals will be compatible with each other. At the very least, any proposed solution to the combination problem should indicate which problems it is addressing, and which problems it is not.
The formulation of the problems above is misleading in one respect. I have typically said “how do microexperiences come together to yield X”, or perhaps “how do microsubjects” or “how do microqualities”. However, constitutive panpsychism is not committed to the claim that macroexperience is wholly grounded in microexperience. It could be partly grounded in causal or structural relations among the microexperiences, or in other microphysical properties, or even in other quiddities if there are non-phenomenal quiddities as well. We can put all this by saying that constitutive panpsychism requires macroexperiences to be wholly grounded in microexperiences and microphysics, where microphysics is understood broadly to include all of the above. The formulations of the relevant problems can then all take the form “How do microexperiences and microphysics come together to yield X?”. With the problems understood this way, the panpsychist has more resources to play with, but the problems still seem very difficult to solve. . . . ."
This is the most interesting paper I've yet read by Chalmers.
". . . There are a few other aspects of the combination problem, corresponding to different aspects of macroexperience that need explaining. There is the unity problem: how do microexperiences come together to yield a unified consciousness? There is the boundary problem (Rosenberg 1998): how do microexperiences come together to yield a bounded consciousness? There is the awareness problem: how do microexperiences come together to yield awareness of qualities? And there is the grain problem (Maxwell 1979; Lockwood 1993): how do microexperiences come together 2Dainton (2011) calls this problem the “derivation problem”. 5 to yield homogeneous macroexperiences, such as a homogeneous experience of red, instead of an enormous jagged array of distinct qualities? Some of these problems might be assimilated to earlier problems (the first three plausibly involve aspects of subjective character, the last involves an aspect of qualitative character, and all involve aspects of structure), but it is useful to have them on the table explicitly.
It is common for a proposed solution to the combination problem to address only one of these problems: most often the subject combination problem and occasionally the quality combination problem. It should be stressed that a satisfactory solution to the combination problem must address all of these problems. This raises the bar for a solution, as it is far from clear that any single proposal can solve all the problems at once. One might appeal to separate proposals for solving the problems one at a time, but then it is far from clear that these proposals will be compatible with each other. At the very least, any proposed solution to the combination problem should indicate which problems it is addressing, and which problems it is not.
The formulation of the problems above is misleading in one respect. I have typically said “how do microexperiences come together to yield X”, or perhaps “how do microsubjects” or “how do microqualities”. However, constitutive panpsychism is not committed to the claim that macroexperience is wholly grounded in microexperience. It could be partly grounded in causal or structural relations among the microexperiences, or in other microphysical properties, or even in other quiddities if there are non-phenomenal quiddities as well. We can put all this by saying that constitutive panpsychism requires macroexperiences to be wholly grounded in microexperiences and microphysics, where microphysics is understood broadly to include all of the above. The formulations of the relevant problems can then all take the form “How do microexperiences and microphysics come together to yield X?”. With the problems understood this way, the panpsychist has more resources to play with, but the problems still seem very difficult to solve. . . . ."
This is the most interesting paper I've yet read by Chalmers.