Further illuminating papers concerning the project of 'naturalizing phenomenology' or, forthrightly in Morris, 'phenomenalizing naturalism'.
1. Dermot Moran on naturalizing phenomenology:
https://philpapers.org/archive/MORLLA.pdf
2.David Morris on same. Following are citations to and extracts from (where accessible) three related papers by Morris. I’ve requested that Morris place the following paper online at academia.edu:
Measurement as Transcendental-Empirical Écart: Merleau-Ponty on Deep
Abstract:
Merleau-Ponty’s radical reflection conceptualizes the transcendental and the empirical as intertwined, emerging only via an écart. I advance this concept of transcendental-empirical écart by studying the problem of measurement in science, in both general and quantum mechanical contexts. Section one analyses scientific problems of measurement, focusing on issues of temporality, to show how measurement entails a transcendental that intertwines/diverges with the empirical. Section two briefly interprets this result via Merleau-Ponty’s concept of depth, to indicate how measurement reveals a temporality that is not an already given ground that would guarantee the transcendental in advance: temporality is instead ‘deep’, it is itself engendered via an écart of transcendental and empirical operations. Section three briefly indicates how these results challenge Meillasoux’s claims about correlationism and ancestrality.
More Info: for special issue on “Merleau-Ponty's Gordian Knot: Transcendental Philosophy, Empirical Science and Naturalism,” eds. Jack Reynolds & Andrew Inkpin (forthcoming in 2017)
Journal Name: Continental Philosophy Review
3. The following paper by Morris is available online at academia.edu, and can be extremely helpful in grasping the significance of natural affordances that enable phenomenological perception via all the senses. Morris’s particular gift, it seems to me, is his ability to clarify the deeper dimensions of what is revealed about the nature of human perception in phenomenological philosophy as ‘built-in’ aspects of the given, in both the time and space/place of existence.
DAVID MORRIS,
Casey’s Subliminal Phenomenology: On Edging Things Back into Place
© David Morris, Department of Philosophy, Concordia University
Published in
Exploring the Work of Edward S. Casey: Giving Voice to Place, Memory, and Imagination, ed. Donald A. Landes & Azucena Cruz-Pierre (Bloomsbury, 2013), 53-61.
Epigraphs:
“External perception is a constant pretension to accomplish something that, by its very nature, it is not in a position to accomplish.” Husserl, Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Syntheses HUA XI 3.5
“The perceived world is the always presupposed foundation of all rationality, all value and all existence. This thesis does not destroy either rationality or the absolute. It only tries to bring them down to earth.” Merleau-Ponty, “The Primacy of Perception and its Philosophical Consequences”, 13.
Morris begins:
“In this chapter I suggest how Casey opens some radical implications for phenomenology. Casey does this by showing that place is what first of all grants room for the appearance of things—but only in virtue of a non-givenness. That is, place undergirds determinate things only in being something “less” than fully delimited or determinate, something less than space would be as an already given dimension. Place is thus kin to Bergson’s
durée as openly generative becoming, in contrast to time as already fixed dimension. In showing us how determinate phenomena are conditioned by place as less than given, and in complementary work on “periphenomena” (see, e.g., WG 438-448), such as glances and edges, Casey reveals what I call a subliminal dimension of phenomena: a way in which periphenomena and thence phenomena appear as delimited only by edging into what is less than delimitable.
This subliminal dimension is phenomenologically paradoxical. It cannot appear as such, precisely because it is less than delimitable, vagrant with respect to classical conditions of appearance. Yet this vagrant “less than” precisely appears as subliminal within and to delimited appearances, versus being something ideal or behind appearances.
Casey thus makes a twofold contribution to phenomenology: bringing phenomena down to earth, as having a determinacy ‘grounded’ in this-here earth-place; and showing how this determinate delimitation involves something subliminal, something non-delimitable and non-given that is nonetheless given within places. Casey’s contribution is obviously complementary to themes of non-givenness in other phenomenologists, and to Heidegger’s turn from temporality to place and
Abgrund (abyss, lack of ground).
But Casey is innovative in his approach and way of displacing non-givenness from temporality into place. To wit, if Bergson shows that we have to wait for the sugar to dissolve, Casey shows that we have to unendingly get back with things into place for them to show themselves. If it is the narrator’s inner effort in Proust’s
À la recherche du temps perdu that exemplifies a Bergsonian waiting for things, then it is
FinnegansWake, with its endless outer circulation through the Dublin landscape/dreamscape that exemplifies Casey’s effort of getting things back into place—and also a kind of vagabond spirit in Casey that runs pell-mell in their wake, to glimpse them edgewise in their “plurabilities.” (
Finnegans Wake is a touchstone of WG.) By putting himself in the wake of things and of place as less than already delimited, Casey suggests what I call a subliminal phenomenology, that, as discussed below, permutes phenomenology’s method and topic. What I offer here is my own synthesis of things learnt from Casey, through sketches that gradually lay out the phenomenological and methodological stakes, and then work into the nexus of things, places and periphenomena to build my case. My synthesis stems in particular from study of Casey’s place work; chapters 3 and 4 in WG, as distinguishing the glance and the gaze and correlative differences in the determinacy of their object (see esp. 139-147); and the discussion of the “logic of the lesser” in WG’s concluding thoughts but also in draft chapters of the forthcoming WE.
Before I begin, two quick clarifications. First, when I talk about the non-givenness of place, I do not mean that place is not given at all. Far from it, place is most evidently given—but it is given as place precisely by not being fully given as to its determinacy. Place thus contrasts with space, which is precisely and in principle constituted as a fully determinate network of locations already capable of locating things in advance. To give an analogy, we readily grasp the mistake in speaking of time as if it is, in the sense of being a thing that could already be fully given. Time, or better,
durée, is precisely in the making, time is never fully now. Similarly, Casey shows that place is never fully here. Place is what grants there being a determinate here or there, but place grants does so in being given on the go, in inherently leading itself out in what I call Procession . Place thus manifests a determinate here precisely in being “less than” fully here—something that Casey teaches us, particularly in his “logic of the lesser.”
Second, because points about non-givenness are inherently difficult, yet a bit more familiar to us as they erupt in durée, I often work with the above analogy between duree and place. But this is not meant to give durée either parity with or priority over place. Casey is displacing temporality from its privileged position in traditional philosophy by showing us the priority of place. (Indeed, without place we could not notice movement or time.) Nonetheless, the analogy helps.
Getting Back With the Things Themselves—In Place.
Phenomenology famously calls on philosophy to go back to the things themselves. Yet Husserl’s own effort to do so eventually reveals things as at once exceeding us yet being less than we took them to be. Consider perceiving something quite mundane, this lemon sitting on the counter. It looks to be given right over there. But, as Merleau-Ponty would put it, to perceive a lemon is to attend upon a thing present only in inexhaustibly turning up new aspects. A lemon shows up as truly being a lemon only insofar as its showings could possibly reveal, say, a fake, foam lemon; it is there only in the temporal incompleteness of ongoingly showing up as not otherwise than a lemon. Or consider Hollis Frampton’s film
Lemon, in which a lemon shows up in slowly rotating in and out of an eclipsing shadow that its surface casts over itself when lit.
Lemon helps us notice a place-based (vs. temporal) incompletion of things, namely how the very skin through which things show up inherently obscures or edges out their showing up all at once in place.
A thing’s givenness as determinately this or that thus rests on: what is otherwise (its turning up as not fake, etc., in temporality); and otherwhere (its turning up through other aspects now eclipsed, in place). Thus Husserl’s point that by its very nature “[e]xternal perception is a constant pretension to accomplish something that … it is not in a position to accomplish.”
Perception claims to get things in the flesh, to grasp their pith and marrow. Yet in perception the delimited, determinate givenness of objects arises only out of what, as otherwise and otherwhere, is not fully delimited or determinate. This is one of phenomenology’s great discoveries. Even greater is phenomenology’s insight that this is not a defect in things but a transcendental, that is, inherently unsurpassable, condition of their appearance. This upends Descartes’s argument that since appearance is inherently and unendingly incomplete, the real identity of something such as a candle could only be given in an idea, which alone can fully comprehend a thing’s determinacy once and for all. It also marks a turning point in a certain history of philosophy, from a claim that what is truly real must rest in something more than what is now given (e.g., in Platonist or Cartesian ideas that exceed appearances), to the discovery that what gives our sense of reality is something less than and in what now appears given. Indeed, phenomenology radically reconfigures classic philosophical problems of appearance and reality. For the Cartesian, the real conditions of something cannot appear, since appearance cannot bear the full blown determinacy and certainty that Cartesian truth demands. The phenomenologist, on the contrary, has the radically empirical project of finding the real conditions of things in appearance, and finds that these conditions do appear. But these conditions appear only by being something peculiarly less than the full determinacy or certainty that philosophy had previously sought. The paradoxical and difficult point here is that the condition of appearance is not a given thing, substance, essence, idea, etc, but a kind of non-givenness given right within the given.
In phenomenology, this non-givenness classically turns out to be temporality. But Casey shows us how the determinate appearance of things turns on place as a generative non-givenness. If Bergson’s first move is to rise above the turn of experience, to get out of the lock-step of clocktime and into the durée of things, Casey’s first move is to get back into the place in which we first encounter things. And for Casey this means getting out of our lock on things as being determinately all over there, a point we’ll come back to and that comes to the fore for Casey in periphenomena. Altogether, Casey’s way of getting back with the things in place has ontological and methodological consequences, since it subverts the givenness of things, by leading into what I called the subliminal dimension. This connection between place, things, philosophical method, and something bigger than us is more or less explicit in Casey’s article “Sym-Phenomenologizing: Talking Shop.” The article is avowedly about the need to do phenomenology together with other people in workshops, in sym-pathy. But there he writes (drawing on Heidegger on region and place) that “where a workshop, including a workshop in phenomenology, takes place is not indifferent to what is accomplished in that workshop. The place or region is not the mere setting – which could in principle be found anywhere – but part of the process and the product of being in a workshop.”
Now Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and others would already acknowledge that phenomenology’s method of getting back to things takes guidance from and is thence passive to things. This is what opens room for a temporal non-givenness in their phenomenology: getting back to things under the guidance of things takes time. Casey is adding that getting back to things under their guidance takes place. Phenomenology is not just a working together with things or with people, but with place, in a sort of sympathetic wandering that is placial kin to a Bergsonian intuition of duree.
On this front, Casey’s contribution is radical precisely because it shows how non-givenness comes from outside: while we could think that the non-givenness of temporality springs from a sort of insufficiency or passivity internal to the subject, we cannot think this with place. The non-givenness of place indicates a kind of passivity or sympathy that we have, even as reflecting philosophers, with something much bigger than us. Hence my image above of Casey’s phenomenology as methodologically vagabond or subliminal in its edgewise, peripheral approach to things, from their periphery and in their wake (vs. a more traditional head-long approach to abstract things in their essence). . . . .”
Casey’s Subliminal Phenomenology: On Edging Things Back into Place
4. A third paper by Morris that I recommend because Morris here shows a potential naturalization of phenomenology, or phenomenalisation of nature, as implicit in deep structures of Merleau-Ponty’s later phenomenology. MP’s concepts of a)
‘chirality’ [which seems to parallel, and might have inspired, Kafatos’s ontological theory of nature and consciousness], and b) the resulting
‘chiasmic’ character of the intertwining of consciousness and nature/world seem to me to completely overcome Cartesian duality and the resulting ‘mind/body’ problem.
The Chirality of Being: Exploring a Merleau-Ponteian Ontology of Sense
David Morris, Department of Philosophy, Concordia University,
[email protected]/DavidMorris
Published in
Chiasmi International: Trilingual Studies Concerning Merleau-Ponty’s Thought
12 (2011): 165-182.
Abstract
The problem of ontology includes the problem of how being is determinate and has sense, i.e., orientations, meanings, differences that make a difference. This paper explores the thought that being’s sense stems from an ‘ontological chirality,’ a kind of ontological difference with characteristics kin to differences between left and right hands. The paper first shows how Merleau-Ponty’s ontology of reversibility leads to issues of chirality. Results in chemistry, biology and geometry are then discussed to illuminate the importance of chiral differences and to develop a definition of ontological chirality that connects with an ontology of sense.
Morris begins this paper as follows:
"
Being is. But being is also something, it is determinate. The problem of ontology is not only or so much saying how it is that being is, but how it is that being is determinate: how being has orientations, senses, meanings, differences that make a difference, rather than being an indifferent blank void of all sensible determinations. This paper explores the thought that being’s sense stems from an ‘ontological chirality,’ a kind of ontological difference with characteristics kin to differences between left and right hands. The concept of reversibility in Merleau-Ponty’s later ontology led me to this thought, so I begin by briefly showing how chirality lurks within reversibility—especially in a relation between activity and passivity that is crucial to reversibility. I then discuss results in chemistry, biology and geometry to illuminate the importance of chiral differences and to develop a definition of ontological chirality that connects with an ontology of sense.
Reversibility, a concept central to Merleau-Ponty’s later works “Eye and Mind” (OE) and The Visible and the Invisible (VI), indicates both a relational structure and its ontology. For Merleau-Ponty the perceiver and the perceived in general are reversible. He often illustrates this with touch. . . . .”
The Chirality of Being: Exploring a Merleau-Ponteian Ontology of Sense
5. This excellent paper by another phenomenologist is also significant for the naturalisation/phenomenalisation project:
DAVID STOREY, Spirit and/or Flesh: Merleau-Ponty’s Encounter with Hegel
http://phaenex.uwindsor.ca/ojs/leddy/index.php/phaenex/article/viewFile/604/745
ETA: All of the above papers are essential reading for understanding the meaning of/the significance of 'transcendence' in modern philosophy as it develops from Kant through the development of phenomenological philosophy.
Further note: the two papers referenced below are also likely to be helpful as we pursue this 'naturalisation/phenomenalisation project:
“Beyond the Gap,” Petitot, Varela et al:
J. Petitot (1999). Beyond the Gap: An Introduction to Naturalizing Phenomenology in Petitot J., Varela JF, Pachoud B., Roy JM. In Jean Petitot, Franscisco J. Varela, Barnard Pacoud & Jean-Michel Roy (eds.),
Naturalizing Phenomenology. Stanford University Press. (This is the collection of essays to which the videotaped lectures by Zahavi, Moran, and Morris responded at the symposium in Denmark.)
FSU Libraries | Find it @ FSU
and
Toward a Pragmatically Naturalist Metaphysics of the Fact-Value Entanglement
Sami Pihlström
Journal of Philosophical Research 35:323-352 (2010) {available in whole at the link below}
Abstract
This paper examines the metaphysical status of the fact-value entanglement. According to Hilary Putnam, among others, this is a major theme in both classical and recent pragmatism, but its relevance obviously extends beyond pragmatism scholarship. The pragmatic naturalist must make sense of the entanglement thesis within a broadly non-reductively naturalist account of reality. Two rival options for such metaphysics are discussed: values may be claimed to emerge from facts (or normativity from factuality), or fact and value may be considered continuous. Thus, pragmatic naturalism about fact and value may be based on either emergentism or Peircean synechism. This is a crucial tension not only in pragmatist philosophy of value but in pragmatically naturalist metaphysics generally.
http://www.nordprag.org/papers/Pihlstrom - Pragmatic Metaphysics of the Fact-Value Entanglement.pdf