• NEW! LOWEST RATES EVER -- SUPPORT THE SHOW AND ENJOY THE VERY BEST PREMIUM PARACAST EXPERIENCE! Welcome to The Paracast+, eight years young! For a low subscription fee, you can download the ad-free version of The Paracast and the exclusive, member-only, After The Paracast bonus podcast, featuring color commentary, exclusive interviews, the continuation of interviews that began on the main episode of The Paracast. We also offer lifetime memberships! Flash! Take advantage of our lowest rates ever! Act now! It's easier than ever to susbcribe! You can sign up right here!

    Subscribe to The Paracast Newsletter!

Consciousness and the Paranormal — Part 9

Free episodes:

Status
Not open for further replies.
Boy, Dennet is so smart that he manages to avoid having consciousness emerge from physical processes. Brilliant. How does he manage this!? By (still) denying that consciousness exists haha.

"This brings us to the question of consciousness, on which Dennett holds a distinctive and openly paradoxical position. Our manifest image of the world and ourselves includes as a prominent part not only the physical body and central nervous system but our own consciousness with its elaborate features—sensory, emotional, and cognitive—as well as the consciousness of other humans and many nonhuman species. In keeping with his general view of the manifest image, Dennett holds that consciousness is not part of reality in the way the brain is. Rather, it is a particularly salient and convincing user-illusion, an illusion that is indispensable in our dealings with one another and in monitoring and managing ourselves, but an illusion nonetheless.

You may well ask how consciousness can be an illusion, since every illusion is itself a conscious experience—an appearance that doesn’t correspond to reality. So it cannot appear to me that I am conscious though I am not: as Descartes famously observed, the reality of my own consciousness is the one thing I cannot be deluded about. The way Dennett avoids this apparent contradiction takes us to the heart of his position, which is to deny the authority of the first-person perspective with regard to consciousness and the mind generally.

The view is so unnatural that it is hard to convey, but it has something in common with the behaviorism that was prevalent in psychology at the middle of the last century. Dennett believes that our conception of conscious creatures with subjective inner lives—which are not describable merely in physical terms—is a useful fiction that allows us to predict how those creatures will behave and to interact with them. He has coined the term “heterophenomenology” to describe the (strictly false) attribution each of us makes to others of an inner mental theater—full of sensory experiences of colors, shapes, tastes, sounds, images of furniture, landscapes, and so forth—that contains their representation of the world.

According to Dennett, however, the reality is that the representations that underlie human behavior are found in neural structures of which we know very little. And the same is true of the similar conception we have of our own minds. That conception does not capture an inner reality, but has arisen as a consequence of our need to communicate to others in rough and graspable fashion our various competencies and dispositions (and also, sometimes, to conceal them):

Curiously, then, our first-person point of view of our own minds is not so different from our second-person point of view of others’ minds: we don’t see, or hear, or feel, the complicated neural machinery churning away in our brains but have to settle for an interpreted, digested version, a user-illusion that is so familiar to us that we take it not just for reality but also for the most indubitable and intimately known reality of all.

The trouble is that Dennett concludes not only that there is much more behind our behavioral competencies than is revealed to the first-person point of view—which is certainly true—but that nothing whatever is revealed to the first-person point of view but a “version” of the neural machinery. In other words, when I look at the American flag, it may seem to me that there are red stripes in my subjective visual field, but that is an illusion: the only reality, of which this is “an interpreted, digested version,” is that a physical process I can’t describe is going on in my visual cortex.

I am reminded of the Marx Brothers line: “Who are you going to believe, me or your lying eyes?” Dennett asks us to turn our backs on what is glaringly obvious—that in consciousness we are immediately aware of real subjective experiences of color, flavor, sound, touch, etc. that cannot be fully described in neural terms even though they have a neural cause (or perhaps have neural as well as experiential aspects). And he asks us to do this because the reality of such phenomena is incompatible with the scientific materialism that in his view sets the outer bounds of reality. He is, in Aristotle’s words, “maintaining a thesis at all costs.”"


Actually, Dennett shows precisely how our notion of consciousness in the "form" (which we generate for ourselves) is an illusion. The very notion we "gather" along the rules of our own language and "logic" is actually a caricature of the dynamic self-reinforcing processes of the physical elements that produce our sense of "being"-- Dennett is just overstating a point to the end of showing us just how powerful our own minds create a static object to ourselves that represents a dynamic interplay of a small part of the universe with itself (i.e. infinitesimally small body and brain that grew directly out of the universe). The conceit we continue to worship is the notion that the very mechanism that causes us to be self-aware is itself beyond the rules of mechanical cause-effect relations for which we discover (using our own mechanism of cognition). We think that since we have comprehended cause-effect relations in the world to satisfy our narrow needs and goals that we have therefore answered the same regarding our own bodies...but cognitive dissonance prevails because we still think of the universe as an "artifact" created by some supernal being (without realizing of course that the same question applies to the supernal, etc). Strange that we would demand a being like ourselves as a pre-requisite for "existence" when we ourselves had no choice in the specifics of how we came into "being" (you didn't choose your birthday...unless of course you are willing to expand your phenomenal self model to the entire universe...which is possible...but no one else will understand your experience even if you felt it)

Throw away all of the philosophical banter and papers for the moment and just breath ....count what you yourself cannot explain regarding the difference between "deciding" to take a breath and "involuntarily" breathing...there is a "chiasm" you get to experience every day, but you will forget it when you move on to your next task. The same can be said for hunger, driving, working (skillfully, without thinking) and just "existing"...somehow you convince yourself that all of those things you decided to do....but you are really a "do-happening" (Alan Watts)...the boundary between the voluntary and involuntary is ...you.


Dennett is really trying to show that the plenum of physical reality is sufficient for creating our condition...i.e. that our understanding of the mechanisms (i.e. because we keep regarding them as such...) is what bars our own comprehension. To be sure, any ontological category (regardless of its name or the analogy we applied to understand it), whether it be pure "mind" or "matter" would fail to help us understand the dynamics of our own ability to "feel" and "experience" existence. That is because the model we apply to explain our own situation is itself a product of our ability to relate to the world of things which precedes the very mechanisms, language, logic, etc., which we attempt to use to accomplish our understanding. Even the word "understanding" is derived from an accepted wordless concept of "standing" on a ground....the process assumes an agent who can discern his relation with such "ground" without even having any doubt of such relations. All of our words assume a structure of being as a foundation that requires no explanation. Only our own needs (arbitrary) are satisfied by such constructions...(i.e. go get water...) -- our existence and ability to communicate the methods and means to others (like ourselves) through symbols does not require full comprehension to be useful. Simply put, we can drink water without knowing that it is made of hydrogen and oxygen...or eat without understanding the role of the element "Carbon" in the reaction chains that convert these things into our own ability to continue existing.
 
Dennett is really trying to show that the plenum of physical reality is sufficient for creating our condition...i.e. that our understanding of the mechanisms (i.e. because we keep regarding them as such...) is what bars our own comprehension.
Right. He's not denying consciousness exists so much as he's denying it exists as an ontologically distinct thing/object/substance.

This take on Hegel comes to mind again:

"What Hegel argues is that what seems to us as given in immediate sensation is anything but; to focus on a "bit" of sensation, say a patch of color or a flavor, is not to grasp an object-like thing, but to actually experience an underlying process. Colors and tastes change in intensity; so do all of our sensory perceptions and concepts in thought. What seems to us as a fixed and orderly Being is unmasked as a deeper process of historically-unfolding becoming."

My issue with Dennet's position is the stance that the Q domain is really real while everything else we experience is a phenomenon. The line he draws seems arbitrary. I think Hoffman's stance as far as where the line is (i.e. there is no line) makes more sense.

Anyhow I also agree with Strawson who says we don't know enough about this stuff we call the physical to say it isn't inherently conscious.

In a way this fits with Dennet, although he wouldn't see it this way: If he doesn't believe consciousness emerges nor is a distinct substance, then... consciousness just is primary?

Eh, panpsychism?
 
Last edited:
Right. He's not denying consciousness exists so much as he's denying it exists as an ontologically distinct thing/object/substance.

This take on Hegel comes to mind again:

"What Hegel argues is that what seems to us as given in immediate sensation is anything but; to focus on a "bit" of sensation, say a patch of color or a flavor, is not to grasp an object-like thing, but to actually experience an underlying process. Colors and tastes change in intensity; so do all of our sensory perceptions and concepts in thought. What seems to us as a fixed and orderly Being is unmasked as a deeper process of historically-unfolding becoming."

My issue with Dennet's position is the stance that the Q domain is really real while everything else we experience is a phenomenon. The line he draws seems arbitrary. I think Hoffman's stance as far as where the line is (i.e. there is no line) makes more sense.

Anyhow I also agree with Strawson who says we don't know enough about this stuff we call the physical to say it isn't inherently conscious.

In a way this fits with Dennet, although he wouldn't see it this way: If he doesn't believe consciousness emerges nor is a distinct substance, then... consciousness just is primary?

Eh, panpsychism?

What you are calling "ontological distinct things", i.e. our "categories," we have to remember are constructions (i.e. simulations, abstractions...) which live solely in the very "thing" we are trying to explain (namely the generator of such constructs, categories,...). The very methods which help our cognition apply such "distinctions" are themselves functions of the infrastructure (our brains, body, etc) we are trying to grok.

So in that respect, we can easily dismiss "consciousness" as an "ontologically distinct thing" since the very apparatus to perform such distinctions are in and of themselves presumed before we take on the task (of understanding, explaining, etc).

What is the "Q domain" in the light of the above comments?
 
What you are calling "ontological distinct things", i.e. our "categories," we have to remember are constructions (i.e. simulations, abstractions...) which live solely in the very "thing" we are trying to explain (namely the generator of such constructs, categories,...).
Right. Mind and matter are indeed concepts. We can accept that they are indeed just concepts, while at the same time also accepting that the HP identifies a problem with unifying these concepts.

(Although as we've discussed there are other concepts that allow us to move past the HP.)

The very methods which help our cognition apply such "distinctions" are themselves functions of the infrastructure (our brains, body, etc) we are trying to grok.
Right. But we have to recognize that brains and bodies are also perceptual and conceptual "abstractions" by this logic.

So in that respect, we can easily dismiss "consciousness" as an "ontologically distinct thing" since the very apparatus to perform such distinctions are in and of themselves presumed before we take on the task (of understanding, explaining, etc).
Hm, I don't follow you here.

We can or we can't dismiss consciousness as ontologically distinct from matter?

Why are why can't we? Because the apparatus are presumed before we ask the question?

What is the "Q domain" in the light of the above comments?
Quantum. Dennet says everything we experience is a phenomenon except for quantum mechanics. QM is apparently the noumenal in his view.
 
This take on Hegel comes to mind again:

"What Hegel argues is that what seems to us as given in immediate sensation is anything but; to focus on a "bit" of sensation, say a patch of color or a flavor, is not to grasp an object-like thing, but to actually experience an underlying process. Colors and tastes change in intensity; so do all of our sensory perceptions and concepts in thought. What seems to us as a fixed and orderly Being is unmasked as a deeper process of historically-unfolding becoming."

What is the source/text of that extract? Thanks.
 
The ‘hard problem of consciousness’ is thus not a problem that emerges from consciousness at all, it is a problem that depends upon the materialistic mythos that was so successful for the physical sciences in previous centuries. Only if you think the universe is fundamentally made up of bits of inanimate stuff are you surprised that there are clumps of matter that have unique experiences. If you think the universe is fundamentally made up of events, as Whitehead does, the hard problem vanishes as a philosophical artefact – exactly as Dennett suggests, but for precisely opposite reasons.

I don't think he provides the link from process to experience, but it can be found in a discussion of Whitehead's panpsychism:

But roughly speaking Whitehead proposed a radical reform of our conception of the fundamental nature of the world, placing events(or items that are more event-like than thing-like) and the ongoing processes of their creation and extinction as the core feature of the world, rather than the traditional triad of matter, space and time. His panpsychism arises from the idea that the elementary events that make up the world (which he called occasions) partake of mentality in some—often extremely attenuated—sense, metaphorically expressed in terms of the mentalistic notions of creativity, spontaneity and perception.

Panpsychism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

In very general terms, Whitehead's panpsychism faces the same objections as any other version, and stems from the same basic anti-emergentist intuition (for a clear introduction to, and defense of, Whitehead's panpsychism see Griffin 1998; another interpretation, and pantheistic reworking, can be found in the writings of Charles Hartshorne (1897-2000), for example, in Hartshorne 1972).
 
Last edited:
I found the comments regarding molecular genetics very interesting. I'd like to see more on that. Is he talking about epigenetics? Do we necessarily get that far away from materialism though with epigenetics or even QM?
 
I found the comments regarding molecular genetics very interesting. I'd like to see more on that. Is he talking about epigenetics? Do we necessarily get that far away from materialism though with epigenetics or even QM?

Materialism (mechanism-ism, to maybe coin a phrase) in the sense of the ethos ... has that really changed? Billiard-ballism, yes, I think hasn't led to any advances since Lavoisier, but who is using billiard ball models anymore?
 
Actually, Dennett shows precisely how our notion of consciousness in the "form" (which we generate for ourselves) is an illusion. The very notion we "gather" along the rules of our own language and "logic" is actually a caricature of the dynamic self-reinforcing processes of the physical elements that produce our sense of "being"-- Dennett is just overstating a point to the end of showing us just how powerful our own minds create a static object to ourselves that represents a dynamic interplay of a small part of the universe with itself (i.e. infinitesimally small body and brain that grew directly out of the universe). The conceit we continue to worship is the notion that the very mechanism that causes us to be self-aware is itself beyond the rules of mechanical cause-effect relations for which we discover (using our own mechanism of cognition). We think that since we have comprehended cause-effect relations in the world to satisfy our narrow needs and goals that we have therefore answered the same regarding our own bodies...but cognitive dissonance prevails because we still think of the universe as an "artifact" created by some supernal being (without realizing of course that the same question applies to the supernal, etc). Strange that we would demand a being like ourselves as a pre-requisite for "existence" when we ourselves had no choice in the specifics of how we came into "being" (you didn't choose your birthday...unless of course you are willing to expand your phenomenal self model to the entire universe...which is possible...but no one else will understand your experience even if you felt it)

Throw away all of the philosophical banter and papers for the moment and just breath ....count what you yourself cannot explain regarding the difference between "deciding" to take a breath and "involuntarily" breathing...there is a "chiasm" you get to experience every day, but you will forget it when you move on to your next task. The same can be said for hunger, driving, working (skillfully, without thinking) and just "existing"...somehow you convince yourself that all of those things you decided to do....but you are really a "do-happening" (Alan Watts)...the boundary between the voluntary and involuntary is ...you.


Dennett is really trying to show that the plenum of physical reality is sufficient for creating our condition...i.e. that our understanding of the mechanisms (i.e. because we keep regarding them as such...) is what bars our own comprehension. To be sure, any ontological category (regardless of its name or the analogy we applied to understand it), whether it be pure "mind" or "matter" would fail to help us understand the dynamics of our own ability to "feel" and "experience" existence. That is because the model we apply to explain our own situation is itself a product of our ability to relate to the world of things which precedes the very mechanisms, language, logic, etc., which we attempt to use to accomplish our understanding. Even the word "understanding" is derived from an accepted wordless concept of "standing" on a ground....the process assumes an agent who can discern his relation with such "ground" without even having any doubt of such relations. All of our words assume a structure of being as a foundation that requires no explanation. Only our own needs (arbitrary) are satisfied by such constructions...(i.e. go get water...) -- our existence and ability to communicate the methods and means to others (like ourselves) through symbols does not require full comprehension to be useful. Simply put, we can drink water without knowing that it is made of hydrogen and oxygen...or eat without understanding the role of the element "Carbon" in the reaction chains that convert these things into our own ability to continue existing.

Yes, but it all works very well, if we let it.

Alan Watts also teaches us how to get out of our own way, which, if you think about it too much, is not only impossible but also puts you firmly back into your own way.

Draw a circle here:
 
This blog and the ensuing discussion in the comments include a number of references and links that I think will be productive for us at this point:

Phenomenology and Process Ontology: Evan Thompson, Merleau-Ponty, Whitehead, and the Growing Together of the Flesh of the World

Further references provided:

Process Approaches to Consciousness
Process Approaches to Consciousness in Psychology, Neuroscience, and Philosophy of Mind

Lecture by David Kleinberg-Levin [link now missing, referred to in the title of the blog; described by the blog author as follows: "... on Merleau-Ponty’s late thought, including his understanding of the elemental flesh of the world. Thinking with Whitehead, I’d argue, can help us follow the late Merleau-Ponty’s desire not only to unify the mind with the flesh of the body, but mind and body with the flesh of the world. In this way, as Levin puts it, things become a prolongation of my body, just as my body becomes a prolongation of the world. The authors of the recently published Nature and Logos: A Whiteheadian Key to Merleau-Ponty’s Fundamental Thought agree with the tremendous potential for cross-fertilization of these two thinkers.]

Isabelle Stengers‘ recently translated book Thinking With Whitehead


.
 
Materialism (mechanism-ism, to maybe coin a phrase) in the sense of the ethos ... has that really changed? Billiard-ballism, yes, I think hasn't led to any advances since Lavoisier, but who is using billiard ball models anymore?

So it isn't the matter in "materialism" we object to ... but the "doesn't matter".

Materialism in the sense of treating everything as material. As "standing reserve" as "human resources" and capital. Would we have imbued "materialism" into the matter(s) of our sciences without this ethos? Or would we have seen, as @Soupie reminds us, that matter can be quite ethereal?

To some tune of Andrew Lloyd Webber:

Oh, it's something quite material,
to see these things ethereal,
overlapping magesterial!!

ooh ahh!

Even the absolute sidereal,
Requests a peek-a-reareal,
Nothing is imperial ...

Cause ... it's ... all ...

(que big finish)

ETHEREAL!

(you try writing lyrics with "ethereal")
 
What you are calling "ontological distinct things", i.e. our "categories," we have to remember are constructions (i.e. simulations, abstractions...) which live solely in the very "thing" we are trying to explain (namely the generator of such constructs, categories,...). The very methods which help our cognition apply such "distinctions" are themselves functions of the infrastructure (our brains, body, etc) we are trying to grok.

So in that respect, we can easily dismiss "consciousness" as an "ontologically distinct thing" since the very apparatus to perform such distinctions are in and of themselves presumed before we take on the task (of understanding, explaining, etc).

What is the "Q domain" in the light of the above comments?

This still sounds like Metzinger.
 
This blog and the ensuing discussion in the comments include a number of references and links that I think will be productive for us at this point:

Phenomenology and Process Ontology: Evan Thompson, Merleau-Ponty, Whitehead, and the Growing Together of the Flesh of the World

Further references provided:

Process Approaches to Consciousness
Process Approaches to Consciousness in Psychology, Neuroscience, and Philosophy of Mind

Lecture by David Kleinberg-Levin [link now missing, referred to in the title of the blog; described by the blog author as follows: "... on Merleau-Ponty’s late thought, including his understanding of the elemental flesh of the world. Thinking with Whitehead, I’d argue, can help us follow the late Merleau-Ponty’s desire not only to unify the mind with the flesh of the body, but mind and body with the flesh of the world. In this way, as Levin puts it, things become a prolongation of my body, just as my body becomes a prolongation of the world. The authors of the recently published Nature and Logos: A Whiteheadian Key to Merleau-Ponty’s Fundamental Thought agree with the tremendous potential for cross-fertilization of these two thinkers.]

Isabelle Stengers‘ recently translated book Thinking With Whitehead


.

I'm going to see if I can find the video mentioned in that post.
 
MP pursued the nature of consciousness in animals. I'll try to find sources for you. He shared Panksepp's recognition that consciousness arises in affectivity.
 
MP pursued the nature of consciousness in animals. I'll try to find sources for you. He shared Panksepp's recognition that consciousness arises in affectivity.

I assume the rest of nature is just (patiently) waiting for us to come back. We do have some modest skills that would help the whole enterprise.
 
This paper is fascinating . . .

Journal for Critical Animal Studies,
Volume IX, Issue 1/2, 2011


Painting the Prehuman: Bataille, Merleau-Ponty, and
the Aesthetic Origins of Humanity

Brett Buchanan

"Nothing must be concealed: what is involved, finally, is a failure of
humanity."

--Georges Bataille,
The Accursed Share II: 14-15

Extract

". . .The striking feature is that with the mastery of the natural world, as evinced in the birth of art, the human is both omnipresent and, at one and the same time, precisely nowhere to be found. The transgression effects an overcoming of animality but one wherein the self-mastery is sorely lacking. At one point Bataille describes this as a paradox, but calling it a
paradox seems too innocent a description. The paradox of the Upper Paleolithic world, he writes in an essay on The Lespugne Venus, is that it gave animals the expressive value of the real, whereas its representations of humans, much more rare, are occasionally formless, even caricatural, occasionally deformed, sometimes disfigured by an animal mask, which eliminates their humanity‖ (107). The transgression occurs when the prehuman foregoes further identification with the animals that have been so evocatively realized, and in doing so witnesses his/her own breaking of solidarity with the natural order (e.g., with the Montespan bear), leading to the extreme point of self-effacement (Guerlac, 2007: 34). The unease with one‘s own image may just as well be a sense of shame rendered in the absence of a reciprocating gaze; an embarrassed blush of reason in the refusal of self-identification.

We are beginning to get to the point where we might question what is really at stake in the supposed birth of humanity. It is starting to look like a fraught adventure inasmuch as the indeterminacy of the prehuman threatens the positive determination of a certain way of being called ̳human. In an essay on Primitive Art published some 20-30 years earlier than his Lascaux writings (and thus 10 years before Lascaux‘s discovery), Bataille had already put his finger on the issue when he contrasted traditional European art with "the shocking duality at the beginning of figurative representation. Reindeer, bison, and horses are shown with a meticulousness so perfect that if we had similarly scrupulous pictures of men themselves, the remotest period of human development would cease to be the most inaccessible. But the drawings and sculptures that represent the Aurignacians are nearly all formless and much less human than those that represent animals" (40). Why is it that there are no corresponding images of those who painted these images and carved these figures? That the represented animals might be more human than the images of the prehumans, as Bataille notes, likely says more about the artists themselves than the accuracy of the images. . . . ."

https://academicpublishingplatforms...s/volume2/201112281102_JSAC_vol1,2_2011_1.pdf
 
Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze
Brett Buchanan, Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze, State University of New York Press, 2008, 223pp., $75.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780791476116.

Reviewed by Robert Vallier, DePaul University

In the last few years Continental philosophy, in various guises, has rediscovered life. Phenomenologists direct their attention to the lifeworld, and to the phenomena of life and living beings. Some poststructuralists "deconstruct" the difference between organic and inorganic, while others concern themselves with germinal and viroid life and propose various biophilosophies, and still others talk about life as that to which 'biopower' is directed. And most evidently, if we take recent book catalogues as an index, there is a great deal of interest in animality (here I don't refer to animal rights or ethics, which have also given rise to much reflection and debate, but rather the question of animal being) to think about the animal in itself, and about the original difference between animal and human being, thus in some way clarifying the special status of the latter which many, since Aristotle, have determined to be both rational and political. What so much -- it would be unfair to say all -- of this resuscitated interest has in common is a striking disregard for the sciences of life, all too easily dismissing them as predicated on an unreflected and non-philosophical concept of life, which, the standard narrative goes, is inevitably reduced to some form of (neo-)vitalism, (neo-)mechanism, or (neo-)finalism. That may or may not be true as a criticism of the life-sciences, but it certainly should not constitute an excuse to avoid a careful reading of and thoughtful engagement with their theoretical research and experimental findings, which seems so often to be symptomatic of this return to life.

It is precisely in this regard that Brett Buchanan's Onto-Ethologies marks a difference. As suggested by the subtitle ("The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze"), Buchanan endeavors to show how the theoretical findings of the properly experimental work of one particular scientist -- the important Swiss biologist, Jakob von Uexküll, sometimes called "the father of ethology" -- made their way into and helped to shape the itineraries of three major Continental philosophers. This alone makes it a valuable contribution to the growing body of literature on life-philosophy generally, and animality in particular. Given that it is written with a great deal of clarity and attention to detail, the book will certainly repay careful study.

It is easy to forget in our day the radicality of the contribution that Uexküll made in his, which is why in the first chapter Buchanan examines Uexküll's life and work, situating him with respect to the historical and scientific context of his time. Darwin's notion of natural selection was still subject to much debate among biologists, and Uexküll himself worried that, as conceived by Darwin, the model relied far too heavily on causal mechanism and mechanistic (physical) laws of nature. By reducing biological processes to physical mechanisms, Darwin and others like him miss whatever is particular to biological life and thus eliminating vitalism. That Uexküll may have largely shared this objection, common to the many different schools of vitalism, does not by itself commit him to a vitalist position. On the contrary, as Buchanan argues, Uexküll was also quite critical of both the argument that held that some natural animating principle or force subtended all life, and the argument that contended that life was directed towards some end or telos. The major representative of the teleological camp was Baer, whose arguments against Darwinism had significant influence on Uexküll, as did his peculiar, morphological notion of teleology that each organism develops according to a plan. For Baer, this plan is neither some pregiven rational concept nor the presupposition of nature's purposiveness; the plan is grounded in the organism itself, and more precisely, on the specific arrangement of its components. Although this rings Kantian to our ears, Uexküll heard in it the announcement of a double path beyond Kant (by whom he is undeniably inspired): first, the role played by the animal body (and particularly its proprioreceptivity), and second, the relations of living beings to other objects they encounter. He altogether rejects the notion of purpose or purposiveness in nature. It's on the basis of this double path beyond Kant, on the one hand, and his arguments against mechanism, on the other, that he will be able to sketch out a notion of the plan that life follows. Central to this is his concept of the Umwelt, the environing or surrounding world, which proved to be the key to all his subsequent research and which was later influential for Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze, and many others.

The animal has an Umwelt, surrounding and enclosing it, much like a soap bubble. Each animal has its own Umwelt, and one soap bubble may enclose many others within it or be enclosed in other, larger bubbles. Unlike Leibniz's monads, these bubbles have windows, or at least intersect and interact with each other in concrete ways. The Umwelt is not merely given, but rather produced by the animal through the functioning of its body, its sensory and instinctual apparatus, and the objects it encounters. Uexküll devotes years of his productive life to the study of the Umwelt, its formation, and how it constitutes a ground for understanding animal being. From this research, several astonishing examples emerge, most famously the behavior of the tick; but more than that, two major theoretical constructs also come to the fore. First, the plan of nature constitutes a kind of melody. An extensive musical metaphor or "theory of the music of life" runs throughout Uexküll's work, and later becomes important to Merleau-Ponty later on. Buchanan neatly summarizes and translates the metaphors, but misses an opportunity to return to and evaluate another philosophical source for Uexküll, namely, Leibniz. The soap bubbles may not be monads, but they exist in a kind of pre-established harmony in the composition of nature. It is this harmonious composition that constitutes the plan of nature, or better, the plan is a kind of musical score. Deleuze later characterized Uexküll as a "Spinozist of affects." Given this, it seems that the background of modern philosophy from Descartes to Kant would be a particularly fecund area to mine in order to understand better the rise of modern biology. Buchanan can't be faulted for not developing this background, for to do so would have doubled the manuscript. While some mention of it could have been helpful, the absence of it stands as an invitation to his readers to engage in further research in this direction.

The second major theoretical construct to emerge from Uexküll's research on the Umwelt is the notion of biosemiotics (Uexküll himself does not use this word, it is retrospectively assigned to him): the notion that animal behavior signifies, and that this signification differentially constitutes its Umwelt as a meaningful world for it (and in so far as signification is directed outwards, for others as well, others who are capable of interpreting the signs, be they other animals or humans). Buchanan does a fine job showing what biosemiotics is and how it is developed by Uexküll and his later readers. For me, this is one of the most interesting and exciting of Uexküll's contributions. Strangely, Buchanan never really returns to this notion in a comprehensive or thematic way. He alludes to it indirectly in the chapters on Heidegger when he speaks of language. But he doesn't take it up in the chapters on Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze, both of whom address the theme in significant ways. One could argue that Merleau-Ponty's second lecture course on Nature (replete with philosophical studies of Uexküll, Lorenz, Portmann, Driesch, and others) has as one of its principal axes of investigation the notion of biosemiotics and animal signification. Similarly, though Deleuze rejects the unitary organism in favor of multiplicities and rhizomes, symbiotes and hybrids, he relates the fragmentary elements of all of these differentially to one another to constitute a meaningful assemblage. In other words, differential elements signify. It seems to me that some version of biosemiotics would be useful for us to better understand how rhizomatic assemblages are structured. Were I asked to state one single criticism of Buchanan's book, it would be the general disappearance of this theme of biosemiotics after the first chapter. But once again, we can view this less a fault and more an invitation to his readers to think along with him the influence Uexküll's theoretical and experiential works have had on contemporary Continental philosophy.

Chapters two and three -- nearly half of the book -- are devoted to a very close reading of Heidegger's somewhat equivocal mention of and interest in Uexküll in his famous 1929/1930 lecture course, part of which is devoted to the question of animal being. In the lectures Uexküll made his infamous and oft-misunderstood claim that "the animal is poor in world." If a moment ago I singled out the greatest weakness of the book, I do not hesitate to add that the book's greatest strength is Buchanan's close, careful, and extraordinarily lucid reading of Heidegger. Both expert and novice will profit from Buchanan's reading, which moves in a habile manner from the texts from the early 1920s to Being and Time to the 29/30 course, while also passing through and critically commenting on the many biological thinkers whom Heidegger mentions during this very productive decade. It becomes quite clear that Heidegger's interest in animality is less to determine its essential being, which he always seems to leave in suspense, but rather in the notion of "world," so that he might clarify the fundamental existential structure of Dasein as "being-in-the-world" through a comparative study. The very close reading of the relevant sections of the 29/30 course is clear and sober, and instead of propagating "heideggerese," clarifies it, cautiously examining and explaining every substantive claim in light of both Heidegger's overall project during these years and Uexküll's contribution (especially his notion of the Umwelt) to that project. I believe that these two chapters will (or should) become a standard secondary source for all those who want to question and understand Heidegger's analytic of animality and its relation to Dasein. That said, Buchanan at one point contends that those (like Lowith, Sartre, Jonas, and Merleau-Ponty, to name just a few) who have rued that Heidegger pays scant heed to the body in Being and Time would gain much from close attention to what he says of animal being. I am not yet quite convinced by that claim. Certainly they would gain something, but the human body and embodiment, is qualitatively different from animality, and this difference is not simply a function of the degree and kind of world that Dasein has and is in, and in which animals are poor. Heidegger is always a bit cagey, I think, about the exact nature of that difference, and while Being and Time may be, as some claim, a wholly new and ontological description of embodiment, Heidegger does leave the originary structure of the body itself -- animal and human -- in suspense. Nonetheless, Buchanan's helpful clarification and interpretation will certainly contribute in productive ways to the on-going debate about the role of the body in Heidegger's thought.

The last two chapters are on Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze, respectively. They are far more restrained in terms of their scope and development. The chapter on Merleau-Ponty concerns the "Theme of the Animal Melody." It traces Uexküll's musical metaphors in Merleau-Ponty's itinerary, starting from The Structure of Behavior. Although Uexküll is mentioned only once in that book in passing, Buchanan artfully shows that his musical ideas play a key role in the development of the argument, following it through the second lecture course on Nature, but mostly skipping over it in The Phenomenology of Perception. As I said earlier, it would have been very useful for Buchanan to take up again the notion of biosemiotics, as Merleau-Ponty is quite keen on developing a "symbolism of the human body," which, were it not for his untimely demise, might have responded to the question that Heidegger leaves in suspense. But Buchanan also follows the echo of Uexküll's melody through the working notes of The Visible and the Invisible, proposing some ways in which these notions contribute to his last ontology. I might disagree with a number of points of Buchanan's reading of these notes and his characterization of Merleau-Ponty's project. However, this is not a failure of the book, but rather one of its finer values. It invites the reader into a critical dialogue with the texts in a way that has not been excessively overworked in the secondary literature. Such dialogue can only lead to new insights.

The chapter on Deleuze constitutes something like a foil, in that Deleuze explicitly and vigorously reinterprets, and sometimes even rejects, the central notions of Uexküll's thought. The soap bubble in which the animal is enclosed bursts, as Buchanan puts it, allowing Deleuze to develop a whole new apparatus for understanding animal being. The animal in its environment is a distinct animal and a distinct environment (and naturally the preposition "in" disappears completely), but rather as a hybrid or a rhizomatic apparatus.The being of the wasp can not be understood independently of the orchid, and it's not the case that the two beings are simply added together to form one compound being composed of two parts. Rather, the wasp and the orchid are a hybrid that is deployed across territories and milieus (a term that is also radically reinterpreted by Deleuze). If Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty remain close to Uexküll's thought, drawing inspiration for it and using it to advance their own itineraries, Deleuze transforms Uexküll's thought in order to create new concepts. Again, one might find something to disagree with in Buchanan's reading of Deleuze, but more importantly, one always finds something to think about (in this case, the transformation of Uexküllian concepts into Deleuzian notions, something I did not expect to find there). It generates discussion, and that is a mark of a good book.

All things considered, Buchanan's book is a compelling and interesting read that makes a real contribution to the growing interest in life-philosophy and living being, and will appeal not only to Continentalists for its insights, but also the Analytics for its clarity and careful construction, and to philosophers of science of all stripes for its careful and nuanced blend of scientific and philosophical writers.

Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze // Reviews // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // University of Notre Dame
 
Status
Not open for further replies.
Back
Top