• NEW! LOWEST RATES EVER -- SUPPORT THE SHOW AND ENJOY THE VERY BEST PREMIUM PARACAST EXPERIENCE! Welcome to The Paracast+, eight years young! For a low subscription fee, you can download the ad-free version of The Paracast and the exclusive, member-only, After The Paracast bonus podcast, featuring color commentary, exclusive interviews, the continuation of interviews that began on the main episode of The Paracast. We also offer lifetime memberships! Flash! Take advantage of our lowest rates ever! Act now! It's easier than ever to susbcribe! You can sign up right here!

    Subscribe to The Paracast Newsletter!

Consciousness and the Paranormal

Free episodes:

Status
Not open for further replies.
Matter is usually a label we fix to a black box existential from which we derive our notion of "knowledge" from the interactions between these black boxes and others. This knowledge is usually not about the thing itself, but that regarding the scenarios and situations for which the thing dwells. So by asking the question, I am really asking what it means to have "knowledge" about matter...but notice that the label changes when we've found its subcomponents, no longer dealing with a "black box" we subdivide our previous "??" into a bunch of other baby-?s--at this point we move our label "matter" down the scale and then fixate on new "black boxes" for which we continue to process and confuse our "knowledge" regarding their interoperations with others as well as potential divisions and relations within them (i.e. when they cease to become black...and are transparent).

So the knowledge label seems to be an artificial construct of the virtual machine...or GUI of consciousness.

The only thing we ever "know" about "matter" is the situations for which we can remove the label "matter"--in this way to "know" about "matter" is to really dissolve the question into smaller units.

And of course, that's just "it", the black box is a progressive illusion of inescapable developmental relevance to us. As we subdivide all environmental attributes that we are "faced" with, knowledge, with relevance to the environment we survive within, is a matter (pun intended!) of progressively transient adaption. Another such black box would be fire. So in this sense, raw knowledge is like a progressive evolutionary key for which we have only our imaginations to unlock it's potential continuum of relevance for us. The key is always elementary, as are fire, water, and shelter. What we do with this basic environmental progressive adaptability the we possess comes from within us based on our physical, mental, and spiritual needs, instinctively. It's my opinion that mankind instinctively realizes that physicality is an absolute detriment to survival. We are constantly pushed from within to overcome all environmental survival threats. I can think of no greater vulnerability than physicality. It's mortality rate is exceptionally high. ;) Mankind will eventually overcome it's physical limitations as certainly as all life is evolutionarily progressive. It is the most potential objective of all living things, and yet it takes real faith to envision with any level of certain conviction.
 
Yesterday in a response to Soupie I referenced the article on Consciousness at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and said that I would c&p here Section 4 of that article identifying seven primary aspects or features of consciousness which I think we must be able to account for in an adequate theory of consciousess. I forgot to provide that material and then lost my internet connection again, but here it is:


4. The descriptive question: What are the features of consciousness?
The What question asks us to describe and model the principal features of consciousness, but just which features are relevant will vary with the sort of consciousness we aim to capture. The main properties of access consciousness may be quite unlike those of qualitative or phenomenal consciousness, and those of reflexive consciousness or narrative consciousness may differ from both. However, by building up detailed theories of each type, we may hope to find important links between them and perhaps even to discover that they coincide in at least some key respects.

4.1 First-person and third-person data
The general descriptive project will require a variety of investigational methods (Flanagan 1992). Though one might naively regard the facts of consciousness as too self-evident to require any systematic methods of gathering data, the epistemic task is in reality far from trivial (Husserl 1913).

First-person introspective access provides a rich and essential source of insight into our conscious mental life, but it is neither sufficient in itself nor even especially helpful unless used in a trained and disciplined way. Gathering the needed evidence about the structure of experience requires us both to become phenomenologically sophisticated self-observers and to complement our introspective results with many types of third-person data available to external observer (Searle 1992, Varela 1995, Siewert 1998)

As phenomenologists have known for more than a century, discovering the structure of conscious experience demands a rigorous inner-directed stance that is quite unlike our everyday form of self-awareness (Husserl 1929, Merleau-Ponty 1945). Skilled observation of the needed sort requires training, effort and the ability to adopt alternative perspectives on one's experience.

The need for third-person empirical data gathered by external observers is perhaps most obvious with regard to the more clearly functional types of consciousness such as access consciousness, but it is required even with regard to phenomenal and qualitative consciousness. For example, deficit studies that correlate various neural and functional sites of damage with abnormalities of conscious experience can make us aware of aspects of phenomenal structure that escape our normal introspective awareness. As such case studies show, things can come apart in experience that seem inseparably unified or singular from our normal first-person point of view (Sacks 1985, Shallice 1988, Farah 1995).

Or to pick another example, third-person data can make us aware of how our experiences of acting and our experiences of event-timing affect each other in ways that we could never discern through mere introspection (Libet 1985, Wegner 2002). Nor are the facts gathered by these third person methods merely about the causes or bases of consciousness; they often concern the very structure of phenomenal consciousness itself. First-person, third-person and perhaps even second-person (Varela 1995) interactive methods will all be needed to collect the requisite evidence.

Using all these sources of data, we will hopefully be able to construct detailed descriptive models of the various sorts of consciousness. Though the specific features of most importance may vary among the different types, our overall descriptive project will need to address at least the following seven general aspects of consciousness (sections 4.2–4.7).

4.2 Qualitative character
Qualitative character is often equated with so called “raw feels” and illustrated by the redness one experiences when one looks at ripe tomatoes or the specific sweet sapor one encounters when one tastes an equally ripe pineapple (Locke 1688). The relevant sort of qualitative character is not restricted to sensory states, but is typically taken to be present as an aspect of experiential states in general, such as experienced thoughts or desires (Siewert 1998).

The existence of such feels may seem to some to mark the threshold for states or creatures that are really conscious. If an organism senses and responds in apt ways to its world but lacks such qualia, then it might count as conscious at best in a loose and less than literal sense. Or so at least it would seem to those who take qualitative consciousness in the “what it is like” sense to be philosophically and scientifically central (Nagel 1974, Chalmers 1996).

Qualia problems in many forms—Can there be inverted qualia? (Block 1980a 1980b, Shoemaker 1981, 1982) Are qualia epiphenomenal? (Jackson 1982, Chalmers 1996) How could neural states give rise to qualia? (Levine 1983, McGinn 1991)—have loomed large in the recent past. But the What question raises a more basic problem of qualia: namely that of giving a clear and articulated description of our qualia space and the status of specific qualia within it.

Absent such a model, factual or descriptive errors are all too likely. For example, claims about the unintelligibility of the link between experienced red and any possible neural substrate of such an experience sometimes treat the relevant color quale as a simple and sui generis property (Levine 1983), but phenomenal redness in fact exists within a complex color space with multiple systematic dimensions and similarity relations (Hardin 1992). Understanding the specific color quale relative to that larger relational structure not only gives us a better descriptive grasp of its qualitative nature, it may also provide some “hooks” to which one might attach intelligible psycho-physical links.

Color may be the exception in terms of our having a specific and well developed formal understanding of the relevant qualitative space, but it is not likely an exception with regard to the importance of such spaces to our understanding of qualitative properties in general (Clark 1993, P.M. Churchland 1995). (See the entry on qualia.)

4.3 Phenomenal structure
Phenomenal structure should not be conflated with qualitative structure, despite the sometimes interchangeable use of “qualia” and “phenomenal properties” in the literature. “Phenomenal organization” covers all the various kinds of order and structure found within the domain of experience, i.e., within the domain of the world as it appears to us. There are obviously important links between the phenomenal and the qualitative. Indeed qualia might be best understood as properties of phenomenal or experienced objects, but there is in fact far more to the phenomenal than raw feels. As Kant (1787), Husserl (1913), and generations of phenomenologists have shown, the phenomenal structure of experience is richly intentional and involves not only sensory ideas and qualities but complex representations of time, space, cause, body, self, world and the organized structure of lived reality in all its conceptual and nonconceptual forms.

Since many non-conscious states also have intentional and representational aspects, it may be best to consider phenomenal structure as involving a special kind of intentional and representational organization and content, the kind distinctively associated with consciousness (Siewert 1998). (See the entry on representational theories of consciousness).

Answering the What question requires a careful account of the coherent and densely organized representational framework within which particular experiences are embedded. Since most of that structure is only implicit in the organization of experience, it can not just be read off by introspection. Articulating the structure of the phenomenal domain in a clear and intelligible way is a long and difficult process of inference and model building (Husserl 1929). Introspection can aid it, but a lot of theory construction and ingenuity are also needed.

There has been recent philosophical debate about the range of properties that are phenomenally present or manifest in conscious experience, in particular with respect to cognitive states such as believing or thinking. Some have argued for a so called “thin” view according to which phenomenal properties are limited to qualia representing basic sensory properties, such as colors, shapes, tones and feels. According to such theorists, there is no distinctive “what-it-is-likeness” involved in believing that Paris is the capital of France or that 17 is a prime number (Tye, Prinz 2012). Some imagery, e.g. of the Eiffel Tower, may accompany our having such a thought, but that that is incidental to it and the cognitive state itself has no phenomenal feel. On the thin view, the phenomenal aspect of perceptual states as well is limited to basic sensory features; when one sees an image of Winston Churchill, one's perceptual phenomenology is limited only to the spatial aspects of his face.

Others holds a “thick” view according to which the phenomenology of perception includes a much wider range of features, and cognitive states as well have a distinctive phenomenology (Strawson 2003, Pitt 2004, Seigel 2010). On the thick view, the what-it-is-likeness of perceiving an image of Marilyn Monroe includes one's recognition of her history as part of the felt aspect of the experience, and beliefs and thoughts as well can and typically do have a distinctive nonsensory phenomenology. Both sides of the debate are well represented in the volume Cognitive Phenomenology (Bayne and Montague 2010).

4.4 Subjectivity
Subjectivity is another notion sometimes equated with the qualitative or the phenomenal aspects of consciousness in the literature, but again there are good reason to recognize it, at least in some of its forms, as a distinct feature of consciousness—related to the qualitative and the phenomenal but different from each. In particular, the epistemic form of subjectivity concerns apparent limits on the knowability or even the understandability of various facts about conscious experience (Nagel 1974, Van Gulick 1985, Lycan 1996).

On Thomas Nagel's (1974) account, facts about what it is like to be a bat are subjective in the relevant sense because they can be fully understood only from the bat-type point of view. Only creatures capable of having or undergoing similar such experiences can understand their what-it's-likeness in the requisite empathetic sense. Facts about conscious experience can be best incompletely understood from an outside third person point of view, such as those associated with objective physical science. A similar view about the limits of third-person theory seems to lie behind claims regarding what Frank Jackson's (1982) hypothetical Mary, the super color scientist, could not understand about experiencing red because of her own impoverished history of achromatic visual experience.

Whether facts about experience are indeed epistemically limited in this way is open to debate (Lycan 1996), but the claim that understanding consciousness requires special forms of knowing and access from the inside point of view is intuitively plausible and has a long history (Locke 1688). Thus any adequate answer to the What question must address the epistemic status of consciousness, both our abilities to understand it and their limits (Papineau 2002, Chalmers 2003). (See the entry on self-knowledge).

4.5 Self-perspectival organization
The perspectival structure of consciousness is one aspect of its overall phenomenal organization, but it is important enough to merit discussion in its own right. Insofar as the key perspective is that of the conscious self, the specific feature might be called self-perspectuality. Conscious experiences do not exist as isolated mental atoms, but as modes or states of a conscious self or subject (Descartes 1644, Searle 1992, though pace Hume 1739). A visual experience of a blue sphere is always a matter of there being some self or subject who is appeared to in that way. A sharp and stabbing pain is always a pain felt or experienced by some conscious subject. The self need not appear as an explicit element in our experiences, but as Kant (1787) noted the “I think” must at least potentially accompany each of them.

The self might be taken as the perspectival point from which the world of objects is present to experience (Wittgenstein 1921). It provides not only a spatial and temporal perspective for our experience of the world but one of meaning and intelligibility as well. The intentional coherence of the experiential domain relies upon the dual interdependence between self and world: the self as perspective from which objects are known and the world as the integrated structure of objects and events whose possibilities of being experienced implicitly define the nature and location of the self (Kant 1787, Husserl 1929).

Conscious organisms obviously differ in the extent to which they constitute a unified and coherent self, and they likely differ accordingly in the sort or degree of perspectival focus they embody in their respective forms of experience (Lorenz 1977). Consciousness may not require a distinct or substantial self of the traditional Cartesian sort, but at least some degree of perspectivally self-like organization seems essential for the existence of anything that might count as conscious experience. Experiences seem no more able to exist without a self or subject to undergo them than could ocean waves exist without the sea through which they move. The Descriptive question thus requires some account of the self-perspectival aspect of experience and the self-like organization of conscious minds on which it depends, even if the relevant account treats the self in a relatively deflationary and virtual way (Dennett 1991, 1992).

4.6 Unity
Unity is closely linked with the self-perspective, but it merits specific mention on its own as a key aspect of the organization of consciousness. Conscious systems and conscious mental states both involve many diverse forms of unity. Some are causal unities associated with the integration of action and control into a unified focus of agency. Others are more representational and intentional forms of unity involving the integration of diverse items of content at many scales and levels of binding (Cleeremans 2003).

Some such integrations are relatively local as when diverse features detected within a single sense modality are combined into a representation of external objects bearing those features, e.g. when one has a conscious visual experience of a moving red soup can passing above a green striped napkin (Triesman and Gelade 1980).

Other forms of intentional unity encompass a far wider range of contents. The content of one's present experience of the room in which one sits depends in part upon its location within a far larger structure associated with one's awareness of one's existence as an ongoing temporally extended observer within a world of spatially connected independently existing objects (Kant 1787, Husserl 1913). The individual experience can have the content that it does only because it resides within that larger unified structure of representation. (See the entry on unity of consciousness.)

Particular attention has been paid recently to the notion of phenomenal unity (Bayne 2010) and its relation to other forms of conscious unity such as those involving representational, functional or neural integration. Some have argued that phenomenal unity can be reduced to representational unity (Tye 2005) while others have denied the possibility of any such reduction (Bayne 2010).

4.7 Intentionality and transparency
Conscious mental states are typically regarded as having a representational or intentional aspect in so far as they are about things, refer to things or have satisfaction conditions. One's conscious visual experience correctly represents the world if there are lilacs in a white vase on the table (pace Travis 2004), one's conscious memory is of the attack on the World Trade Center, and one's conscious desire is for a glass of cold water. However, nonconscious states can also exhibit intentionality in such ways, and it is important to understand the ways in which the representational aspects of conscious states resemble and differ from those of nonconscious states (Carruthers 2000). Searle (1990) offers a contrary view according to which only conscious states and dispositions to have conscious states can be genuinely intentional, but most theorists regard intentionality as extending widely into the unconscious domain. (See the entry on consciousness and intentionality.)

One potentially important dimension of difference concerns so called transparency, which is an important feature of consciousness in two interrelated metaphoric senses, each of which has an intentional, an experiential and a functional aspect.

Conscious perceptual experience is often said to be transparent, or in G.E. Moore's (1922) phrase “diaphanous”. We transparently “look through” our sensory experience in so far as we seem directly aware of external objects and events present to us rather than being aware of any properties of experience by which it presents or represents such objects to us. When I look out at the wind-blown meadow, it is the undulating green grass of which I am aware not of any green property of my visual experience. (See the entry on representational theories of consciousness.) Moore himself believed we could become aware of those latter qualities with effort and redirection of attention, though some contemporary transparency advocates deny it (Harman 1990, Tye 1995, Kind 2003).

Conscious thoughts and experiences are also transparent in a semantic sense in that their meanings seem immediately known to us in the very act of thinking them (Van Gulick 1992). In that sense we might said to ‘think right through’ them to what they mean or represent. Transparency in this semantic sense may correspond at least partly with what John Searle calls the “intrinsic intentionality” of consciousness (Searle 1992).

Our conscious mental states seem to have their meanings intrinsically or from the inside just by being what they are in themselves, by contrast with many externalist theories of mental content that ground meaning in causal, counterfactual or informational relations between bearers of intentionality and their semantic or referential objects.

The view of conscious content as intrinsically determined and internally self-evident is sometimes supported by appeals to brain in the vat intuitions, which make it seem that the envatted brain's conscious mental states would keep all their normal intentional contents despite the loss of all their normal causal and informational links to the world (Horgan and Tienson 2002). There is continued controversy about such cases and about competing internalist (Searle 1992) and externalist views (Dretske 1995) of conscious intentionality.

Though semantic transparency and intrinsic intentionality have some affinities, they should not be simply equated, since it may be possible to accommodate the former notion within a more externalist account of content and meaning. Both semantic and sensory transparency obviously concern the representational or intentional aspects of consciousness, but they are also experiential aspects of our conscious life. They are part of what it's like or how it feels phenomenally to be conscious. They also both have functional aspects, in so far conscious experiences interact with each other in richly content-appropriate ways that manifest our transparent understanding of their contents.

4.8 Dynamic flow
The dynamics of consciousness are evident in the coherent order of its ever changing process of flow and self-transformation, what William James (1890) called the “stream of consciousness.” Some temporal sequences of experience are generated by purely internal factors as when one thinks through a puzzle, and others depend in part upon external causes as when one chases a fly ball, but even the latter sequences are shaped in large part by how consciousness transforms itself.

Whether partly in response to outer influences or entirely from within, each moment to moment sequence of experience grows coherently out of those that preceded it, constrained and enabled by the global structure of links and limits embodied in its underlying prior organization (Husserl 1913). In that respect, consciousness is an autopoietic system, i.e., a self-creating and self-organizing system (Varela and Maturana 1980).

As a conscious mental agent I can do many things such as scan my room, scan a mental image of it, review in memory the courses of a recent restaurant meal along with many of its tastes and scents, reason my way through a complex problem, or plan a grocery shopping trip and execute that plan when I arrive at the market. These are all routine and common activities, but each involves the directed generation of experiences in ways that manifest an implicit practical understanding of their intentional properties and interconnected contents (Van Gulick 2000).

Consciousness is a dynamic process, and thus an adequate descriptive answer to the What question must deal with more than just its static or momentary properties. In particular, it must give some account of the temporal dynamics of consciousness and the ways in which its self-transforming flow reflects both its intentional coherence and the semantic self-understanding embodied in the organized controls through which conscious minds continually remake themselves as autopoietic systems engaged with their worlds.

A comprehensive descriptive account of consciousness would need to deal with more than just these seven features, but having a clear account of each of them would take us a long way toward answering the “What is consciousness?” question.


Consciousness (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
 
Last edited:
Matter is usually a label we fix to a black box existential from which we derive our notion of "knowledge" from the interactions between these black boxes and others. This knowledge is usually not about the thing itself, but that regarding the scenarios and situations for which the thing dwells. So by asking the question, I am really asking what it means to have "knowledge" about matter...but notice that the label changes when we've found its subcomponents, no longer dealing with a "black box" we subdivide our previous "??" into a bunch of other baby-?s--at this point we move our label "matter" down the scale and then fixate on new "black boxes" for which we continue to process and confuse our "knowledge" regarding their interoperations with others as well as potential divisions and relations within them (i.e. when they cease to become black...and are transparent).

So the knowledge label seems to be an artificial construct of the virtual machine...or GUI of consciousness.

The only thing we ever "know" about "matter" is the situations for which we can remove the label "matter"--in this way to "know" about "matter" is to really dissolve the question into smaller units.

I had to look up 'GUI' and found this chart at wikipedia. Would this chart be a serviceable visual aid you could use in clarifying your viewpoint about the position of consciousness relative to what can be counted as 'knowledge' of 'reality'?

640px-Linux_kernel_INPUT_OUPUT_evdev_gem_USB_framebuffer.svg.png
 
Last edited:
I had to look up 'GUI' and found this chart at wikipedia. Would this chart be a serviceable visual aid you could use in clarifying your viewpoint about the position of consciousness relative to what can be counted as 'knowledge' of 'reality'?

640px-Linux_kernel_INPUT_OUPUT_evdev_gem_USB_framebuffer.svg.png

GUI = "Graphical User Interface"

Or as a "wrapper" (another typical computer science term) on the elements of reality which are "given." The chart you provided shows the many levels (some transparent when the user is familiar with them) between the human and HID (human interface devices) through the hardware to interact with the SW "virtual machine" environment...although to us it appears as though we "directly" engage the elements in the UI and graphic overlay (pointing, clicking, dragging and dropping). This is a good analogy on how our own brain interacts with its CNS transparently in order to interact with its own "phenomenal self model" of its environment--to borrow a term from Metzinger (similar to what is called "Virtual Machine" by Dennett)

What I see as "objects" and "matter" are really the wrappings created around given objects to my senses--when those objects are somehow broken apart the sub-components that result are instantly "re-wrapped" accordingly. So what I've really labeled are the temporary containers that wrap my own CNS subsystems that are "coupled" with the surrounding environment.
 
GUI = "Graphical User Interface"

Or as a "wrapper" (another typical computer science term) on the elements of reality which are "given." The chart you provided shows the many levels (some transparent when the user is familiar with them) between the human and HID (human interface devices) through the hardware to interact with the SW "virtual machine" environment...although to us it appears as though we "directly" engage the elements in the UI and graphic overlay (pointing, clicking, dragging and dropping). This is a good analogy on how our own brain interacts with its CNS transparently in order to interact with its own "phenomenal self model" of its environment--to borrow a term from Metzinger (similar to what is called "Virtual Machine" by Dennett)

What I see as "objects" and "matter" are really the wrappings created around given objects to my senses--when those objects are somehow broken apart the sub-components that result are instantly "re-wrapped" accordingly. So what I've really labeled are the temporary containers that wrap my own CNS subsystems that are "coupled" with the surrounding environment.

Being quite tired last night I did not respond to the GUI aspect, although being a computer tinkerer, your comment was well understood. This is pretty much what I have been contending from the beginning, and yes, IMO, it makes total sense. This is how I see the crude breakdown as existing naturally.

Environmental Consciousness
Human Cognition<------ Interfacial Consciousness Interpreter (basis = Temporal Physical Spectral Relativity)
Experience
Primary Environmental Memory Containment (Akashic Record)
Sentient Relevant Alignment
Secondary Waking Experiential Recognition
Secondary Memory Sentient Capture and Recapitulation

I have begun to consider a new and very important addendum to my own fantastic (read: FICTION, at this point) theories. Maybe there is something critically missing between what are Environmental Consciousness & Human Cognition. It is the attraction based process that sets up our emergence within Environmental Consciousness. Primary Centrality.
 
Yesterday in a response to Soupie I referenced the article on Consciousness at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy and said that I would c&p here Section 4 of that article identifying seven primary aspects or features of consciousness which I think we must be able to account for in an adequate theory of consciousess. I forgot to provide that material and then lost my internet connection again, but here it is:


4. The descriptive question: What are the features of consciousness?
The What question asks us to describe and model the principal features of consciousness, but just which features are relevant will vary with the sort of consciousness we aim to capture. The main properties of access consciousness may be quite unlike those of qualitative or phenomenal consciousness, and those of reflexive consciousness or narrative consciousness may differ from both. However, by building up detailed theories of each type, we may hope to find important links between them and perhaps even to discover that they coincide in at least some key respects.

4.1 First-person and third-person data
The general descriptive project will require a variety of investigational methods (Flanagan 1992). Though one might naively regard the facts of consciousness as too self-evident to require any systematic methods of gathering data, the epistemic task is in reality far from trivial (Husserl 1913).

First-person introspective access provides a rich and essential source of insight into our conscious mental life, but it is neither sufficient in itself nor even especially helpful unless used in a trained and disciplined way. Gathering the needed evidence about the structure of experience requires us both to become phenomenologically sophisticated self-observers and to complement our introspective results with many types of third-person data available to external observer (Searle 1992, Varela 1995, Siewert 1998)

As phenomenologists have known for more than a century, discovering the structure of conscious experience demands a rigorous inner-directed stance that is quite unlike our everyday form of self-awareness (Husserl 1929, Merleau-Ponty 1945). Skilled observation of the needed sort requires training, effort and the ability to adopt alternative perspectives on one's experience.

The need for third-person empirical data gathered by external observers is perhaps most obvious with regard to the more clearly functional types of consciousness such as access consciousness, but it is required even with regard to phenomenal and qualitative consciousness. For example, deficit studies that correlate various neural and functional sites of damage with abnormalities of conscious experience can make us aware of aspects of phenomenal structure that escape our normal introspective awareness. As such case studies show, things can come apart in experience that seem inseparably unified or singular from our normal first-person point of view (Sacks 1985, Shallice 1988, Farah 1995).

Or to pick another example, third-person data can make us aware of how our experiences of acting and our experiences of event-timing affect each other in ways that we could never discern through mere introspection (Libet 1985, Wegner 2002). Nor are the facts gathered by these third person methods merely about the causes or bases of consciousness; they often concern the very structure of phenomenal consciousness itself. First-person, third-person and perhaps even second-person (Varela 1995) interactive methods will all be needed to collect the requisite evidence.

Using all these sources of data, we will hopefully be able to construct detailed descriptive models of the various sorts of consciousness. Though the specific features of most importance may vary among the different types, our overall descriptive project will need to address at least the following seven general aspects of consciousness (sections 4.2–4.7).

4.2 Qualitative character
Qualitative character is often equated with so called “raw feels” and illustrated by the redness one experiences when one looks at ripe tomatoes or the specific sweet sapor one encounters when one tastes an equally ripe pineapple (Locke 1688). The relevant sort of qualitative character is not restricted to sensory states, but is typically taken to be present as an aspect of experiential states in general, such as experienced thoughts or desires (Siewert 1998).

The existence of such feels may seem to some to mark the threshold for states or creatures that are really conscious. If an organism senses and responds in apt ways to its world but lacks such qualia, then it might count as conscious at best in a loose and less than literal sense. Or so at least it would seem to those who take qualitative consciousness in the “what it is like” sense to be philosophically and scientifically central (Nagel 1974, Chalmers 1996).

Qualia problems in many forms—Can there be inverted qualia? (Block 1980a 1980b, Shoemaker 1981, 1982) Are qualia epiphenomenal? (Jackson 1982, Chalmers 1996) How could neural states give rise to qualia? (Levine 1983, McGinn 1991)—have loomed large in the recent past. But the What question raises a more basic problem of qualia: namely that of giving a clear and articulated description of our qualia space and the status of specific qualia within it.

Absent such a model, factual or descriptive errors are all too likely. For example, claims about the unintelligibility of the link between experienced red and any possible neural substrate of such an experience sometimes treat the relevant color quale as a simple and sui generis property (Levine 1983), but phenomenal redness in fact exists within a complex color space with multiple systematic dimensions and similarity relations (Hardin 1992). Understanding the specific color quale relative to that larger relational structure not only gives us a better descriptive grasp of its qualitative nature, it may also provide some “hooks” to which one might attach intelligible psycho-physical links.

Color may be the exception in terms of our having a specific and well developed formal understanding of the relevant qualitative space, but it is not likely an exception with regard to the importance of such spaces to our understanding of qualitative properties in general (Clark 1993, P.M. Churchland 1995). (See the entry on qualia.)

4.3 Phenomenal structure
Phenomenal structure should not be conflated with qualitative structure, despite the sometimes interchangeable use of “qualia” and “phenomenal properties” in the literature. “Phenomenal organization” covers all the various kinds of order and structure found within the domain of experience, i.e., within the domain of the world as it appears to us. There are obviously important links between the phenomenal and the qualitative. Indeed qualia might be best understood as properties of phenomenal or experienced objects, but there is in fact far more to the phenomenal than raw feels. As Kant (1787), Husserl (1913), and generations of phenomenologists have shown, the phenomenal structure of experience is richly intentional and involves not only sensory ideas and qualities but complex representations of time, space, cause, body, self, world and the organized structure of lived reality in all its conceptual and nonconceptual forms.

Since many non-conscious states also have intentional and representational aspects, it may be best to consider phenomenal structure as involving a special kind of intentional and representational organization and content, the kind distinctively associated with consciousness (Siewert 1998). (See the entry on representational theories of consciousness).

Answering the What question requires a careful account of the coherent and densely organized representational framework within which particular experiences are embedded. Since most of that structure is only implicit in the organization of experience, it can not just be read off by introspection. Articulating the structure of the phenomenal domain in a clear and intelligible way is a long and difficult process of inference and model building (Husserl 1929). Introspection can aid it, but a lot of theory construction and ingenuity are also needed.

There has been recent philosophical debate about the range of properties that are phenomenally present or manifest in conscious experience, in particular with respect to cognitive states such as believing or thinking. Some have argued for a so called “thin” view according to which phenomenal properties are limited to qualia representing basic sensory properties, such as colors, shapes, tones and feels. According to such theorists, there is no distinctive “what-it-is-likeness” involved in believing that Paris is the capital of France or that 17 is a prime number (Tye, Prinz 2012). Some imagery, e.g. of the Eiffel Tower, may accompany our having such a thought, but that that is incidental to it and the cognitive state itself has no phenomenal feel. On the thin view, the phenomenal aspect of perceptual states as well is limited to basic sensory features; when one sees an image of Winston Churchill, one's perceptual phenomenology is limited only to the spatial aspects of his face.

Others holds a “thick” view according to which the phenomenology of perception includes a much wider range of features, and cognitive states as well have a distinctive phenomenology (Strawson 2003, Pitt 2004, Seigel 2010). On the thick view, the what-it-is-likeness of perceiving an image of Marilyn Monroe includes one's recognition of her history as part of the felt aspect of the experience, and beliefs and thoughts as well can and typically do have a distinctive nonsensory phenomenology. Both sides of the debate are well represented in the volume Cognitive Phenomenology (Bayne and Montague 2010).

4.4 Subjectivity
Subjectivity is another notion sometimes equated with the qualitative or the phenomenal aspects of consciousness in the literature, but again there are good reason to recognize it, at least in some of its forms, as a distinct feature of consciousness—related to the qualitative and the phenomenal but different from each. In particular, the epistemic form of subjectivity concerns apparent limits on the knowability or even the understandability of various facts about conscious experience (Nagel 1974, Van Gulick 1985, Lycan 1996).

On Thomas Nagel's (1974) account, facts about what it is like to be a bat are subjective in the relevant sense because they can be fully understood only from the bat-type point of view. Only creatures capable of having or undergoing similar such experiences can understand their what-it's-likeness in the requisite empathetic sense. Facts about conscious experience can be best incompletely understood from an outside third person point of view, such as those associated with objective physical science. A similar view about the limits of third-person theory seems to lie behind claims regarding what Frank Jackson's (1982) hypothetical Mary, the super color scientist, could not understand about experiencing red because of her own impoverished history of achromatic visual experience.

Whether facts about experience are indeed epistemically limited in this way is open to debate (Lycan 1996), but the claim that understanding consciousness requires special forms of knowing and access from the inside point of view is intuitively plausible and has a long history (Locke 1688). Thus any adequate answer to the What question must address the epistemic status of consciousness, both our abilities to understand it and their limits (Papineau 2002, Chalmers 2003). (See the entry on self-knowledge).

4.5 Self-perspectival organization
The perspectival structure of consciousness is one aspect of its overall phenomenal organization, but it is important enough to merit discussion in its own right. Insofar as the key perspective is that of the conscious self, the specific feature might be called self-perspectuality. Conscious experiences do not exist as isolated mental atoms, but as modes or states of a conscious self or subject (Descartes 1644, Searle 1992, though pace Hume 1739). A visual experience of a blue sphere is always a matter of there being some self or subject who is appeared to in that way. A sharp and stabbing pain is always a pain felt or experienced by some conscious subject. The self need not appear as an explicit element in our experiences, but as Kant (1787) noted the “I think” must at least potentially accompany each of them.

The self might be taken as the perspectival point from which the world of objects is present to experience (Wittgenstein 1921). It provides not only a spatial and temporal perspective for our experience of the world but one of meaning and intelligibility as well. The intentional coherence of the experiential domain relies upon the dual interdependence between self and world: the self as perspective from which objects are known and the world as the integrated structure of objects and events whose possibilities of being experienced implicitly define the nature and location of the self (Kant 1787, Husserl 1929).

Conscious organisms obviously differ in the extent to which they constitute a unified and coherent self, and they likely differ accordingly in the sort or degree of perspectival focus they embody in their respective forms of experience (Lorenz 1977). Consciousness may not require a distinct or substantial self of the traditional Cartesian sort, but at least some degree of perspectivally self-like organization seems essential for the existence of anything that might count as conscious experience. Experiences seem no more able to exist without a self or subject to undergo them than could ocean waves exist without the sea through which they move. The Descriptive question thus requires some account of the self-perspectival aspect of experience and the self-like organization of conscious minds on which it depends, even if the relevant account treats the self in a relatively deflationary and virtual way (Dennett 1991, 1992).

4.6 Unity
Unity is closely linked with the self-perspective, but it merits specific mention on its own as a key aspect of the organization of consciousness. Conscious systems and conscious mental states both involve many diverse forms of unity. Some are causal unities associated with the integration of action and control into a unified focus of agency. Others are more representational and intentional forms of unity involving the integration of diverse items of content at many scales and levels of binding (Cleeremans 2003).

Some such integrations are relatively local as when diverse features detected within a single sense modality are combined into a representation of external objects bearing those features, e.g. when one has a conscious visual experience of a moving red soup can passing above a green striped napkin (Triesman and Gelade 1980).

Other forms of intentional unity encompass a far wider range of contents. The content of one's present experience of the room in which one sits depends in part upon its location within a far larger structure associated with one's awareness of one's existence as an ongoing temporally extended observer within a world of spatially connected independently existing objects (Kant 1787, Husserl 1913). The individual experience can have the content that it does only because it resides within that larger unified structure of representation. (See the entry on unity of consciousness.)

Particular attention has been paid recently to the notion of phenomenal unity (Bayne 2010) and its relation to other forms of conscious unity such as those involving representational, functional or neural integration. Some have argued that phenomenal unity can be reduced to representational unity (Tye 2005) while others have denied the possibility of any such reduction (Bayne 2010).

4.7 Intentionality and transparency
Conscious mental states are typically regarded as having a representational or intentional aspect in so far as they are about things, refer to things or have satisfaction conditions. One's conscious visual experience correctly represents the world if there are lilacs in a white vase on the table (pace Travis 2004), one's conscious memory is of the attack on the World Trade Center, and one's conscious desire is for a glass of cold water. However, nonconscious states can also exhibit intentionality in such ways, and it is important to understand the ways in which the representational aspects of conscious states resemble and differ from those of nonconscious states (Carruthers 2000). Searle (1990) offers a contrary view according to which only conscious states and dispositions to have conscious states can be genuinely intentional, but most theorists regard intentionality as extending widely into the unconscious domain. (See the entry on consciousness and intentionality.)

One potentially important dimension of difference concerns so called transparency, which is an important feature of consciousness in two interrelated metaphoric senses, each of which has an intentional, an experiential and a functional aspect.

Conscious perceptual experience is often said to be transparent, or in G.E. Moore's (1922) phrase “diaphanous”. We transparently “look through” our sensory experience in so far as we seem directly aware of external objects and events present to us rather than being aware of any properties of experience by which it presents or represents such objects to us. When I look out at the wind-blown meadow, it is the undulating green grass of which I am aware not of any green property of my visual experience. (See the entry on representational theories of consciousness.) Moore himself believed we could become aware of those latter qualities with effort and redirection of attention, though some contemporary transparency advocates deny it (Harman 1990, Tye 1995, Kind 2003).

Conscious thoughts and experiences are also transparent in a semantic sense in that their meanings seem immediately known to us in the very act of thinking them (Van Gulick 1992). In that sense we might said to ‘think right through’ them to what they mean or represent. Transparency in this semantic sense may correspond at least partly with what John Searle calls the “intrinsic intentionality” of consciousness (Searle 1992).

Our conscious mental states seem to have their meanings intrinsically or from the inside just by being what they are in themselves, by contrast with many externalist theories of mental content that ground meaning in causal, counterfactual or informational relations between bearers of intentionality and their semantic or referential objects.

The view of conscious content as intrinsically determined and internally self-evident is sometimes supported by appeals to brain in the vat intuitions, which make it seem that the envatted brain's conscious mental states would keep all their normal intentional contents despite the loss of all their normal causal and informational links to the world (Horgan and Tienson 2002). There is continued controversy about such cases and about competing internalist (Searle 1992) and externalist views (Dretske 1995) of conscious intentionality.

Though semantic transparency and intrinsic intentionality have some affinities, they should not be simply equated, since it may be possible to accommodate the former notion within a more externalist account of content and meaning. Both semantic and sensory transparency obviously concern the representational or intentional aspects of consciousness, but they are also experiential aspects of our conscious life. They are part of what it's like or how it feels phenomenally to be conscious. They also both have functional aspects, in so far conscious experiences interact with each other in richly content-appropriate ways that manifest our transparent understanding of their contents.

4.8 Dynamic flow
The dynamics of consciousness are evident in the coherent order of its ever changing process of flow and self-transformation, what William James (1890) called the “stream of consciousness.” Some temporal sequences of experience are generated by purely internal factors as when one thinks through a puzzle, and others depend in part upon external causes as when one chases a fly ball, but even the latter sequences are shaped in large part by how consciousness transforms itself.

Whether partly in response to outer influences or entirely from within, each moment to moment sequence of experience grows coherently out of those that preceded it, constrained and enabled by the global structure of links and limits embodied in its underlying prior organization (Husserl 1913). In that respect, consciousness is an autopoietic system, i.e., a self-creating and self-organizing system (Varela and Maturana 1980).

As a conscious mental agent I can do many things such as scan my room, scan a mental image of it, review in memory the courses of a recent restaurant meal along with many of its tastes and scents, reason my way through a complex problem, or plan a grocery shopping trip and execute that plan when I arrive at the market. These are all routine and common activities, but each involves the directed generation of experiences in ways that manifest an implicit practical understanding of their intentional properties and interconnected contents (Van Gulick 2000).

Consciousness is a dynamic process, and thus an adequate descriptive answer to the What question must deal with more than just its static or momentary properties. In particular, it must give some account of the temporal dynamics of consciousness and the ways in which its self-transforming flow reflects both its intentional coherence and the semantic self-understanding embodied in the organized controls through which conscious minds continually remake themselves as autopoietic systems engaged with their worlds.

A comprehensive descriptive account of consciousness would need to deal with more than just these seven features, but having a clear account of each of them would take us a long way toward answering the “What is consciousness?” question.


Consciousness (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

This is a good framework for the discussion, Constance ... section 4.4 on Subjectivity, links out to another SEP article on self-knowledge that's relevant to the discussion, including a discussion of self-deception:

Self-Knowledge (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

excerpt:

"It seems clear that rational persons may sometimes engage in self-deception: in the face of clear evidence to the contrary, hopes and fears may lead one to believe that her spouse is faithful, or that she is popular, or (even) that she has a fatal disease. However, the idea of self-deception poses conceptual difficulties. The basic problem is that self-deception appears to involve a paradox (Davidson 1985): given that “deception” refers to a deliberate attempt to make someone believe a proposition one believes to be false, self-deception seems to require that one believes the proposition in question to be false. Yet when self-deception succeeds, one (also) believes the proposition in question to be true. And it is doubtful that a rational person can have two explicitly contradictory beliefs."
 
Okay, I want to share some quotes from two of Chalmers papers in which he first gives a broad overview of the various models of phenomenal consciousness and second identifies a few that he think have the best chance of answering the Hard Problem.

The first paper is Consciousness and its Place in Nature . The following quotes will be from this paper until otherwise noted.

First what is phenomenal consciousness and the Hard Problem:

The word 'consciousness' is used in many different ways. It is sometimes used for the ability to discriminate stimuli, or to report information, or to monitor internal states, or to control behavior. We can think of these phenomena as posing the "easy problems" of consciousness. These are important phenomena, and there is much that is not understood about them, but the problems of explaining them have the character of puzzles rather than mysteries. There seems to be no deep problem in principle with the idea that a physical system could be "conscious" in these senses, and there is no obvious obstacle to an eventual explanation of these phenomena in neurobiological or computational terms.

The hard problem of consciousness is the problem of experience. Humans beings have subjective experience: there is something it is like to be them. We can say that a being is conscious in this sense — or is phenomenally conscious, as it is sometimes put — when there is something it is like to be that being. A mental state is conscious when there is something it is like to be in that state. Conscious states include states of perceptual experience, bodily sensation, mental imagery, emotional experience, occurrent thought, and more. There is something it is like to see a vivid green, to feel a sharp pain, to visualize the Eiffel tower, to feel a deep regret, and to think that one is late. Each of these states has a phenomenal character, with phenomenal properties (or qualia) characterizing what it is like to be in the state.[*]
While I'm interested in all aspects of mind, right now I'm really focusing on phenomenal consciousness. This post will mostly address phenomenal consciousness.

Do we truly "know nothing" about consciousness?

There is no question that experience is closely associated with physical processes in systems such as brains. It seems that physical processes give rise to experience, at least in the sense that producing a physical system (such as a brain) with the right physical properties inevitably yields corresponding states of experience. But how and why do physical processes give rise to experience? Why do not these processes take place "in the dark," without any accompanying states of experience? This is the central mystery of consciousness.
There is anecdotal evidence that consciousness/mind can exist "away" from physical systems such as brains - OBE, NDE, ghosts, etc. And while I believe something real is certainly happening, I'm not ready to say that consciousness/minds can exist indefinitely apart from a (physical) system from which it arises. As I've said, it's possible that some minds can arise from (physical) systems that are composed of pure energy a la the photon > matter paper @Constance published awhile back.

Which models does Chalmers think offer the best potential of "maybe" answering the Hard Problem?

A solution to the hard problem would involve an account of the relation between physical processes and consciousness, explaining on the basis of natural principles how and why it is that physical processes are associated with states of experience.

Chalmers paper is very large in scope, and he briefly but thoroughly addresses all the major explanatory models. It's a must read for sure. I'll need to re-read it several times myself. I certainly can't argue for Chalmers so one will have to read his reasoning, but he concludes that materialism - or more particularly physicalism - can't fully account for phenomenal consciousness.

He concludes with an incredible model of consciousness called F-Type Monism which entails a "new" model of the natural world:

Type-F monism is the view that consciousness is constituted by the intrinsic properties of fundamental physical entities: that is, by the categorical bases of fundamental physical dispositions.[*] On this view, phenomenal or protophenomenal properties are located at the fundamental level of physical reality, and in a certain sense, underlie physical reality itself.

...

This view takes its cue from Bertrand Russell's discussion of physics in The Analysis of Matter. Russell pointed out that physics characterizes physical entities and properties by their relations to one another and to us. [ @Michael Allen ] For example, a quark is characterized by its relations to other physical entities, and a property such as mass is characterized by an associated dispositional role, such as the tendency to resist acceleration. At the same time, physics says nothing about the intrinsic nature of these entities and properties. Where we have relations and dispositions, we expect some underlying intrinsic properties that ground the dispositions, characterizing the entities that stand in these relations.[*] But physics is silent about the intrinsic nature of a quark, or about the intrinsic properties that play the role associated with mass. So this is one metaphysical problem: what are the intrinsic properties of fundamental physical systems?

...

At the same time, there is another metaphysical problem: how can phenomenal properties be integrated with the physical world? Phenomenal properties seem to be intrinsic properties that are hard to fit in with the structural/dynamic character of physical theory; and arguably, they are the only intrinsic properties that we have direct knowledge of. Russell's insight was that we might solve both these problems at once. Perhaps the intrinsic properties of the physical world are themselves phenomenal properties. Or perhaps the intrinsic properties of the physical world are not phenomenal properties, but nevertheless constitute phenomenal properties: that is, perhaps they are protophenomenal properties. If so, then consciousness and physical reality are deeply intertwined.

This view holds the promise of integrating phenomenal and physical properties very tightly in the natural world. Here, nature consists of entities with intrinsic (proto)phenomenal qualities standing in causal relations within a spacetime manifold. Physics as we know it emerges from the relations between these entities, whereas consciousness as we know it emerges from their intrinsic nature. As a bonus, this view is perfectly compatible with the causal closure of the microphysical, and indeed with existing physical laws. The view can retain the structure of physical theory as it already exists; it simply supplements this structure with an intrinsic nature. And the view acknowledges a clear causal role for consciousness in the physical world: (proto)phenomenal properties serve as the ultimate categorical basis of all physical causation.
This entire model is fascinating, but what I want to hone in on is the concept of the protophenomenal. I'll touch on this next, but first his concluding comments.

As I see things, the best options for a nonreductionist are type-D dualism, type-E dualism, or type-F monism: that is, interactionism, epiphenomenalism, or panprotopsychism. If we acknowledge the epistemic gap between the physical and the phenomenal, and we rule out primitive identities and strong necessities, then we are led to a disjunction of these three views. Each of the views has at least some promise, and none have clear fatal flaws. For my part, I give some credence to each of them. I think that in some ways the type-F view is the most appealing, but this sense is largely grounded in aesthetic considerations whose force is unclear.

...

In any case, this gives us some perspective on the mind-body problem. It is often held that even though it is hard to see how materialism could be true, materialism must be true, since the alternatives are unacceptable. As I see it, there are at least three prima facie acceptable alternatives to materialism on the table, each of which is compatible with a broadly naturalistic (even if not materialistic) worldview, and none of which has fatal problems. So given the clear arguments against materialism, it seems to me that we should at least tentatively embrace the conclusion that one of these views is correct. Of course all of the views discussed in this paper need to be developed in much more detail, and examined in light of all relevant scientific and philosophical developments, in order to be comprehensively assessed. But as things stand, I think that we have good reason to suppose that consciousness has a fundamental place in nature.
Okay, now to move on to the next paper in which Chalmers discusses panprotopyschism in more detail. I am drawn to this theory because I am drawn to the idea that phenomenal consciousness is directly related to physical systems, monism, and the concept that minds are constituted of what I have called primal units, but which of course Chalmers describes more clearly.

http://consc.net/papers/panpsychism.pdf

Again, I'm just going to quote from a few sections, a full reading the paper is recommended.

On page 7 of the paper, after covering some background, he begins to discuss panpsychism in more detail.

Panpsychism, once again, is the thesis that some microphysical entities are conscious. For our
purposes, it is useful to distinguish various more fine-grained varieties of panpsychism. To do
this, we can first introduce some terminology.

Let us say that macroexperience is the sort of conscious experience had by human beings
and other macroscopic entities (that is, entities that are not fundamental physical entities).
Macroexperience involves the instantiation of macrophenomenal properties: properties
characterizing what it is like to be humans and other macroscopic entities. Let us say that
microexperience is the sort of conscious experience had by microphysical entities.


Microexperience involves the instantiation of microphenomenal properties: properties
characterizing what it is like to be microphysical entities.

If panpsychism is correct, there is microexperience and there are microphenomenal
properties. We are not in a position to say much about what microexperience is like. I think we
can be confident that it is very different from human experience, however. It is almost certainly
much simpler than human experience.
Here is where Chalerms begins to touch on a concept/question that fascinates me: what is the mind "made" of? This is the question I was pursuing early on in this thread which I think befuddled both @smcder and @Constance.

Constitutive panpsychism is the thesis that macroexperience is (wholly or partially)
grounded in microexperience. More or less equivalently, it is the thesis that macroexperience is
constituted by microexperience, or realized by microexperience. On this view,
macrophenomenal truths obtain in virtue of microphenomenal truths, in roughly the same sense
in which materialists hold that macrophenomenal truths obtain in virtue of microphysical truths.

To put things intuitively, constitutive panpsychism holds that microexperiences somehow add
up to yield macroexperience.
The view can allow that macroexperience is not wholly grounded
in microexperience: for example, it might be grounded in microexperience along with certain
further structural or functional properties.
Finally! Hurray! (Although, ultimately, there are no good models of how this might happen...)

Chalmers then goes on to describe a particular model of constitutive panpsychism:

In particular, I will focus on constitutive Russellian panpsychism.

On this view,
microphenomenal properties serve as quiddities, playing the roles associated with microphysical
properties, and also serve as the grounds for macrophenomenal properties. That is,
microexperience constitutes macroexperience while also playing microphysical roles.
On this
view, one could think of the world as fundamentally consisting in fundamental entities bearing
fundamental microphenomenal properties, where these microphenomenal properties are
connected to each other (and perhaps to other quiddities) by fundamental laws with the structure
that the laws of physics describe. All this microphenomenal structure also serves to constitute
the macrophenomenal realm, just as microphysical structure serves to constitute the
macrophysical realm.

I think that constitutive Russellian panpsychism is perhaps the most important form of
panpsychism, precisely because it is this form that promises to avoid the problems of
physicalism and dualism and to serve as a Hegelian synthesis.
Chalmers goes on to discuss some other models and related issues. All of it is recommended reading. Then:

Recall that panprotopsychism is the view that fundamental physical entities are protoconscious.

In more detail, let us say that protophenomenal properties are special properties that
are not phenomenal (there is nothing it is like to have a single protophenomenal property) but
that can collectively constitute phenomenal properties, perhaps when arranged in the right
structure.
Panprotopsychism is then the view that some fundamental physical entities have
protophenomenal properties. ...

One might worry that any non-panpsychist materialism will be a form of panprotopsychism.
After all, non-panpsychist materialism entails that microphysical properties are not phenomenal
properties and that they collectively constitute phenomenal properties. This is an undesirable
result. The thought behind panprotopsychism is that protophenomenal properties are special
properties with an especially close connection to phenomenal properties.
This is the view that I hold.

Chalmers goes on to discuss issues related to these views in great depth. Of particular interest is the "combination" problem which he identifies as the biggest hurdle for constitutive Russellian panpsychism.

It is true that we do not have much idea of what protophenomenal properties are like. For
now they are characterized schematically, in terms of their relation to phenomenal properties. A
fuller account will have to wait for a full panprotopsychist theory, though I will speculate about
one sort of protophenomenal property toward the end of this article. But our ignorance about
protophenomenal properties should not be mistaken for an objection to the truth of
panprotopsychism.

Given Russellian monism as our new synthesis, a more significant antithesis now threatens. This antithesis takes the form of a major problem for both panpsychism and panprotopsychism: the combination problem. ...

Still, I think that the Hegelian argument gives good reason to take both panpsychism and panprotopsychism very seriously. If we can find a reasonable solution to the combination problem for either, this view would immediately become the most promising solution to the mind–body problem. So the combination problem deserves serious and sustained attention.
I think this is an exciting area for exploration and it's where I'll be focusing going forward.

Finally, here is an interesting discussion of "subject" which I don't fully grok via terminology but may conceptually as shared in my last post. I need to explore this further, especially since I'm apparently a Russelian Monist, haha.

A third reaction is to deflate the subject, either denying that experiences must have subjects at all, or at least denying that subjects are metaphysically and conceptually simple entities. I think it is a conceptual truth that experiences have subjects: phenomenal properties must be instantiated by something, and they characterize what it is like to be that thing. But the second denial seems more tenable.

Indeed, some such denial seems required to be a constitutive panpsychist, a constitutive panprotopsychist, or indeed a materialist. This view may require rejecting certain intuitions about subjects, but these intuitions are not non-negotiable.

We might define Subjects as primitive subjects of experience. I think that we have a natural conception of Subjects: these are subjects as they might have been in the Garden of Eden, as it were. I think that where Subjects are concerned, the subject/subject gap and the nonsubject/subject gap are both extremely plausible: the existence of a Subject is not necessitated or a priori entailed by the existence of distinct Subjects or indeed by the existence of non-Subjects. So if we are Subjects (and if we set aside the view that macrosubjects are identical to microsubjects), constitutive panpsychism and constitutive panprotopsychism are false.

Still, it is far from obvious that we are Subjects. There does not seem to be an introspective datum that we are Subjects, and it is not obvious that there are strong theoretical arguments to that effect. There are perhaps intuitions of determinacy about personal identity that tend to support the claim (see Barnett 2010 and Nida-Rümelin 2010), but these intuitions do not seem to be non-negotiable, and there are reasonably strong considerations in favor of rejecting them (see 27
Parfit 1984). And once we deny that we are Subjects, the door is at least opened to rejecting the subject/subject gap and the nonsubject/subject gap, and to accepting constitutive panpsychism or panprotopsychism.

I think that a Russellian monist must almost certainly embrace this view (perhaps the only remotely promising alternative is the quantum version of the micro/macro identity claim above).
 
Last edited:
Very good work, Soupie, in highlighting key points in Chalmers's developing thinking. The part you've added in your edit at 10:42 (the combination problem, the Russelian monism) is apparently where you will carry your commentary further and where we shall want to follow you. I am all ears. I've added notes to various parts of your post in Word and might post some of them after I reread them. Thank you very much for what you've gathered and presented here.
 
GUI = "Graphical User Interface"

Or as a "wrapper" (another typical computer science term) on the elements of reality which are "given." The chart you provided shows the many levels (some transparent when the user is familiar with them) between the human and HID (human interface devices) through the hardware to interact with the SW "virtual machine" environment...although to us it appears as though we "directly" engage the elements in the UI and graphic overlay (pointing, clicking, dragging and dropping). This is a good analogy on how our own brain interacts with its CNS transparently in order to interact with its own "phenomenal self model" of its environment--to borrow a term from Metzinger (similar to what is called "Virtual Machine" by Dennett)

I don't doubt that our brain interacts with the phenomenal world -- the world as it appears to us -- on the basis, in part, of its interconnections with the physical body {what you refer to as a "phenomenal self model"}, but in my view, based in the philosophy I've referred to and in my own experience, consciousness and also mind interact directly with the world in its phenomenal appearances to us, which are enabled by (and no doubt limited by) our sensual and other embodied connections with it. These connections are not, I think, a matter of interaction of one informational 'module' with another, all taking place within the brain. If that were true, why would we experience the world we live in phenomenally, 'feel' our presence to and in its visibility and palpability, interpret it so variously in human societies and cultures, engage with it endlessly in the innumerable forms of human world-directed activity, and 'care' {in the Heideggerian sense} about its and our own 'meaning'?

What I see as "objects" and "matter" are really the wrappings created around given objects to my senses--when those objects are somehow broken apart the sub-components that result are instantly "re-wrapped" accordingly. So what I've really labeled are the temporary containers that wrap my own CNS subsystems that are "coupled" with the surrounding environment.

It seems to me that it is we who, intentionally, break those objects apart in our scientific, philosophical, and artistic interrogation of the world and in the ensuing expression to one another of what we then find. If we continually find complexity beneath our former concepts concerning what-is, that is a fact of our lives as existents -- it is one of the 'existentials' in terms of which we have to negotiate our lives, recognizing the limitations of our knowledge. Nevertheless, our species' history records progress in comprehending the nature of being, our own and that of the world in which we dwell. We can never experience the protophenomenological level of physical being at the microphysical level, but we can think our way through to its reality and understand its foundational significance. This is the work of mind, which is indeed built out of the phenomenal appearances of the world as we have access to them -- and also out of the reflective capacities of consciousness itself to discover its own structure as access to 'things', as Husserl and the other existential-phenomenological philosophers have demonstrated.
 
@Constance - another piece to an earlier discussion on language/thought east/west

... this was just a comment in a talk I listened to recently .., the questioner was trying to understand a concept in Buddhism and the teacher discussed translation, noting that:

Western language was "ontologically based"

and he explicitly included Spanish, French, Italian - but also German, though he said he was most familiar with English

... and Eastern languages were experientially or epistemologically oriented/based ...

... so that the statement that was being read as the way the world is ...


all experience is a dream

... was better understood as an instruction

just another piece ... I haven't found anything more on this -


Sent from my iPhone using Tapatalk
 
Here are references and links to two papers we probably ought to read concerning IIT and the metaphysics of consciousness. Following these, Chalmers responds in part as follows in the comments section:

For what it’s worth, I think it’s not so easy to reconcile IIT itself with type-F monism. Type-F monism standardly requires that the fundamental connection between physics and consciousness lies at the level of fundamental physics, whereas IIT suggests that the fundamental connection is at the level of structural organization above the fundamental level. (The issues here are somewhat connected to the issues that Miguel Sebastian discusses in his paper here on the tension between panpsychism and organizational invariance.) I don’t really see how a version of type-F monism can allow fundamental connections above the fundamental microphysical level (e.g. fundamental phenomenal properties serving as grounds for macrophysical dispositions) without violating microphysical causal closure or else making those phenomenal properties epiphenomenal. And if the fundamental connections are all at the level of microphysics, then it looks like the information integration principle (connecting consciousness in a brain to phi in that brain, say) can’t itself be fundamental. Perhaps it could still be a consequence of fundamental principles that apply only at the microphysical level, but it’s not easy to see how that could work. By contrast it’s much easier to see how a type-E version or a type-B version of the view will go.

posted February 15, 2013 at 16:33 by David Chalmers

Integrated Information Theory and the Metaphysics of Consciousness | Consciousness Online
 
@Constance - another piece to an earlier discussion on language/thought east/west

... this was just a comment in a talk I listened to recently .., the questioner was trying to understand a concept in Buddhism and the teacher discussed translation, noting that:

Western language was "ontologically based"

and he explicitly included Spanish, French, Italian - but also German, though he said he was most familiar with English

... and Eastern languages were experientially or epistemologically oriented/based ...

... so that the statement that was being read as the way the world is ...


all experience is a dream

... was better understood as an instruction

just another piece ... I haven't found anything more on this -

Do you remember the link to the talk you were listening to or the speaker? It seems to me that it might be more precise to say that 'Western language is ontologically overdetermined' rather than that it is ontologically based. Somewhere recently in this thread there was a link to a treatment of the Whorf-Sapir theory and another (or several other) language theorists, which I meant to follow. I'll look for it and post it if it seems to treat the issue you raise.
 
it's an old q&a session on unfetteredmind.org but only one comment in a Long Q&A. the speaker is a Western translator from Tibetan and Pali ... ken McLeod


Sent from my iPhone using Tapatalk
 
@Soupie, in your long wonderful post today you wrote this:

As I've said, it's possible that some minds can arise from (physical) systems that are composed of pure energy a la the photon > matter paper @@Constance published awhile back.

I'm not recalling that paper. Is it possible someone else posted the link to it? In any event, can you link us to it when you get a chance?
 
Soupie, on the subject of color perception, the papers summarized and discussed at this link will probably interest you:

Sapir-Whorf hypothesis was right… about adults « Neuroanthropology

Here is an extract concerning the third paper cited.

. . . Work by Kay’s team focused on the brain hemisphere used to classify colours. They tested subjects by showing them coloured targets randomly in their visual fields, and then seeing how long subjects could shift attention to the targets. As Smith writes:

"It is well known that in adults, perception of colour is processed predominantly by the left hemisphere, which is also where most people process language. Studies have shown that the language one speaks can have an impact on the colour one sees."


Because adults use their left hemisphere to categorize colours, they can do perceptual tasks requiring colour categorization faster in the right visual field (the one that the left hemisphere links to). So, as we might expect, adults could shift to coloured targets in their right visual field faster. A variety of studies suggest that the the faster categorization in the right visual field is the result of influence from the lexical capacities of the left hemisphere. I have no problem with this, although I’m still not entirely persuaded that I want to call the ability to visually shift to coloured targets an act of ‘categorization.’ . . .

The interesting twist on this report is that the team also tested pre-linguistic infants, from four to six month olds. Unlike the adults, the children were able to do perceptual tasks requiring colour categorization faster in the left visual field, suggesting that colour perception is a right hemisphere phenomenon in 4- to 6-month-olds. As the abstract to Franklin et al. (2008) explains: ‘The findings suggest that language-driven [category perception] in adults may not build on prelinguistic [category perception], but that language instead imposes its categories on a [left hemisphere] that is not categorically prepartitioned.’

The article by Smith goes on to discuss a couple of other interesting research papers (one of which I might return to in another post), but I found this instability in colour perception fascinating. The data suggests that there might be a discontinuity in the way that people categorize (and perceive, more importantly) colours between infancy and later life. The pre-linguistic way in which infants perceive colour may not necessarily be the foundation for colour perception later on, once a child learns language.

In other words, instead of having a part of our brain which categorizes colours, we have at least two ways we could do it, one that only emerges after we’ve learned language. I suppose that, at least in the populations that the Berkeley team were testing, the later-to-arise language-related categorizing capacity seems to displace the earlier way of accomplishing the task. Of course, it might not wipe out the earlier capacity, and it might emerge under duress or if there was some organic problem with the left hemisphere, dominant solution (which might be language based).

This seems to me to be a very good example of a simple function being accomplished in diverse ways within the brain, even if one way is dominant under most circumstances. Not so much a colour categorization ‘module’ as a brain that solves perceptual problems with the tools at its resources, using language or a left hemisphere ‘node’ of some sort, when it used to accomplish the same function in a different way before the emergence of the new capacity.
 
Last edited:
Soupie, someone else must have linked the Popular Science article. This is the article on light and matter that I posted, from The Guardian:

Matter will be created from light within a year, claim scientists | Science | The Guardian


Matter will be created from light within a year, claim scientists
By Ian Sample, The Guardian
Sunday, May 18, 2014 14:12 EDT

bigbang.shutterstock.jpg

Topics: demonstrationGregory BreitJohn Wheelersubatomic particles

  • 3707
    In a neat demonstration of E=mc2, physicists believe they can create electrons and positrons from colliding photons

    Researchers have worked out how to make matter from pure light and are drawing up plans to demonstrate the feat within the next 12 months.

    The theory underpinning the idea was first described 80 years ago by two physicists who later worked on the first atomic bomb. At the time they considered the conversion of light into matter impossible in a laboratory.

    But in a report published on Sunday, physicists at Imperial College London claim to have cracked the problem using high-powered lasers and other equipment now available to scientists.

    “We have shown in principle how you can make matter from light,” said Steven Rose at Imperial. “If you do this experiment, you will be taking light and turning it into matter.”

    The scientists are not on the verge of a machine that can create everyday objects from a sudden blast of laser energy. The kind of matter they aim to make comes in the form of subatomic particles invisible to the naked eye.

    The original idea was written down by two US physicists, Gregory Breit and John Wheeler, in 1934. They worked out that – very rarely – two particles of light, or photons, could combine to produce an electron and its antimatter equivalent, a positron. Electrons are particles of matter that form the outer shells of atoms in the everyday objects around us.

    But Breit and Wheeler had no expectations that their theory would be proved any time soon. In their study, the physicists noted that the process was so rare and hard to produce that it would be “hopeless to try to observe the pair formation in laboratory experiments”.

    Oliver Pike, the lead researcher on the study, said the process was one of the most elegant demonstrations of Einstein’s famous relationship that shows matter and energy are interchangeable currencies. “The Breit-Wheeler process is the simplest way matter can be made from light and one of the purest demonstrations of E=mc2,” he said.

    Writing in the journal Nature Photonics, the scientists describe how they could turn light into matter through a number of separate steps. The first step fires electrons at a slab of gold to produce a beam of high-energy photons. Next, they fire a high-energy laser into a tiny gold capsule called a hohlraum, from the German for “empty room”. This produces light as bright as that emitted from stars. In the final stage, they send the first beam of photons into the hohlraum where the two streams of photons collide.

    The scientists’ calculations show that the setup squeezes enough particles of light with high enough energies into a small enough volume to create around 100,000 electron-positron pairs.

    The process is one of the most spectacular predictions of a theory called quantum electrodynamics (QED) that was developed in the run up to the second world war. “You might call it the most dramatic consequence of QED and it clearly shows that light and matter are interchangeable,” Rose told the Guardian.

    The scientists hope to demonstrate the process in the next 12 months. There are a number of sites around the world that have the technology. One is the huge Omega laser in Rochester, New York. But another is the Orion laser at Aldermaston, the atomic weapons facility in Berkshire.

    A successful demonstration will encourage physicists who have been eyeing the prospect of a photon-photon collider as a tool to study how subatomic particles behave. “Such a collider could be used to study fundamental physics with a very clean experimental setup: pure light goes in, matter comes out. The experiment would be the first demonstration of this,” Pike said.

    Andrei Seryi, director of the John Adams Institute at Oxford University, said: “It’s breathtaking to think that things we thought are not connected, can in fact be converted to each other: matter and energy, particles and light. Would we be able in the future to convert energy into time and vice versa?”
Matter will be created from light within a year, claim scientists | Science | The Guardian
 
Last edited:
Last paragraph from that Guardian article:

Andrei Seryi, director of the John Adams Institute at Oxford University, said: “It’s breathtaking to think that things we thought are not connected, can in fact be converted to each other: matter and energy, particles and light. Would we be able in the future to convert energy into time and vice versa?”

Is it possible that time might turn out to be a form of energy or a by-product of energy of several kinds, beginning in the quantum substrate? Our continuous existential sense of temporality certainly propels us forward in our own existences, always at the edge of future moments understood in the context of our "Inner Time Consciousness" as explicated by Husserl. And the incredible 'lightness of being' might turn out to become lighter once we are out of the body, taking the form of the 'light beings' encountered in NDEs.
 
Last edited:
The interesting conclusion to that Popular Science article:

"This isn't the first time light has been converted into matter: in 1997, Stanford's linear collider used a different process that involved large numbers of photons interacting with the help of a high-powered electron beam and an electric field that provided the energy needed to collide the photons to produce matter particles. The Imperial College London team's experiment, by contrast, uses the energy of the two colliding photons themselves—it'll be the first time light has been converted into matter in a total vacuum, thus making the process much easier to observe.

"The idea of creating a photon-photon collider is one that has long interested physicists," says Pike. "Many different particles can be produced in photon collisions, so such a collider could potentially be used to study fundamental physics with a very clean experimental approach. [It] could be used as an antimatter source—useful in PET scanning, for example—as equal numbers of electrons and positrons are formed, but there are much easier and more efficient ways of creating antimatter than this. Applications [of the process] may arise in the future, but at the moment, the main draw of this experiment is certainly academic: observing a very simple process for the first time."

While modern technology finally makes it possible to conduct the Breit-Wheeler process for the first time, Pike says they'll have only just begun to scratch the surface of its capabilities; as lasers become more powerful over time, scientists will be able to produce more and different particles than just positron-electron pairs. He says their initial discovery, though accidental, was ultimately an inevitable scientific advance.

"This process is a little odd in that, theoretically, its validity is not really in any doubt," he says. "It's just that in the past we haven't had any way of detecting it, whereas closely related processes—like the annihilation of an electron and positron into two photons—were seen decades ago. If we hadn't published this work, I'm sure someone at some point in the future would have made efforts to observe it."
 
Status
Not open for further replies.
Back
Top