I don't understand the meaning of that last sentence, but it does seem to me that what you are doing is attempting to use the philosophical terms 'transcend' and 'transcendence' in the service of 1) a strictly analytical interpretation/theorization of what we can only partially (even fragmentarily) understand of the history of the evolution and increasing complexity of nature in our universe, and 2) within that theory to locate a temporally evolved place for consciousness and mind in stage 4 of your conceptual hierarchy. It's not clear what you expect to be the next evolutionary level, your stage 5, and how mind and world are to be evolved from stage 4. What's your best guess about stage 5? It seems to me that, given the preceding four stages you conceive of, there must be some grounds you've established upon which to postulate what will change in stage 5.
The main reason for my responding at this point is to focus discussion on the various ways in which the philosophical terms 'transcend' and 'transcendence' have been understood and used in the history of Western philosophy and particularly in the modern period beginning with the phenomenological turn. The following extract from a paper by Daniel Dahlstrom entitled "Heidegger's Transcendentalism" clarifies key differing usages of the concepts of 'transcendence' that I think you need to be aware of and responsive to in preparing your HCT theory for inevitable critiques by your readers and referees.
". . .transcendence here does not only characterize, as it typically does for
Husserl (at least circa 1913), what lies in some sense beyond the subject
(even if always also immanent or potentially immanent to it).
Instead, the transcendence that makes up the very being of being-here
encompasses a relation to oneself as well as a correlative relatedness
to the world at large. Heidegger attempts to capture this distinctive
transcendence with the metonym, “being-in-the-world.”19 Thus, it is
the very essence of being-here to transcend (range over and charac-
34
terize) itself and the world, others, and any other entities and modes
of being that it encounters within the world. It does so thanks to a
disposed understanding of being. In other words, an understanding of
being as mattering to it existentially constitutes and discloses “the transcendence
of the being of being-here.” Analysis of existence, this self-disclosive
constitution of being-here, yields the transcendental knowledge
that makes up fundamental ontology.
Earlier I noted differences between Heidegger’s and Husserl’s use
of the term ‘transcendence’. Yet the differences should not obscure
some basic homologies. Echoing the cognate central function of transcendental
subjectivity in Husserl’s phenomenology, Heidegger emphasizes
that for the problem of being in general as for the problem of
transcendence “the subjectivity of the subject itself ” is the central question.
20 Heidegger also follows Husserl here and elsewhere in adopting
Kant’s talk of a transcendental sphere providing “conditions of the
possibility” for some other, subordinate level. In a similar vein he
argues that grounding in general necessarily has a transcendental meaning
because it is rooted in Da-sein’s transcendence.21
Indeed, in this last respect there are patent, albeit easily misleading,
parallels among the three philosophers. Thus, in the
Kritik der reinen
Vernunft Kant elaborates the transcendental principles that make empirical
judgments possible and how transcendental idealism at once takes
leave of and ensures commonsense realism; in
Ideen I Husserl outlines
the phenomenological or transcendental reductions that yield transcendental
phenomena capable of explaining transcendence in the very
natural attitude that they suspend; and in
Sein und Zeit Heidegger
demonstrates how what ontologically enables the encounter of innerworldly
entities, namely, the transcendence of the world, is grounded
in “the horizonal unity of ecstatic temporality,” itself the ontological
sense of being-here as its original illumination or clearing.22 While Kant
uses the term ‘transcendence’ to signify a principle that oversteps the
limits of what can be experienced and Husserl uses it to signify experiences
directed beyond themselves, they both sharply distinguish the
respective scope of the term from that which they, again in different
ways, reserve for ‘transcendental’.23 Given their different uses of ‘transcendence’,
we might capture the divergent roles assigned to transcendental
subjectivity in this regard by Kant and Husserl respectively,
as follows. While one of the aims of Kant’s critical analysis of transcendental
subjectivity is to demonstrate the insignificance of transcendent
claims, Husserl’s phenomenological analysis of transcendental
35
subjectivity is meant to explain its transcendence (a transcendence
always perspectivally limited in the case of perceptions of sensory
objects). By contrast, Heidegger retrieves and recasts the medieval sense
of ‘transcendence’ by applying it to Da-sein’s being, while applying
the term ‘transcendental’ to the disclosure (truth) of that transcendence.
Despite these significant variations, there is one final aspect of
Heidegger’s link with his transcendental predecessors that deserves note,
particularly in view of the way that Heidegger subsequently views all
philosophies of transcendence within the shadows of Plato’s interpretation
of being and what Heidegger takes to be its “idealist” legacy.24
Both Kant and Husserl style their philosophies as transcendental idealisms,
precisely to capture the irreducibility of knowledge (and, for
that matter, certain other values) to empirical or naturalistic descriptions
of human behavior or organisms. Herein lies the basic insight
driving Neo-Kantian thinkers, as noted at the outset, but also Heidegger’s
lifelong refrain that “ ‘there is’ being only as long as Dasein is.”25 In
this context, it is telling that Heidegger already in
Sein und Zeit explicitly
links transcendentalism with idealism and even seems willing, under
proper constraints, to allow for a certain understanding of the latter.
To be sure, insofar as realism and idealism frame the traditional debate
in epistemology, he rejects both alike as untenable and their very
dichotomy as ungrounded.
Nonetheless, he lauds idealism as “the sole and legitimate possibility
of philosophical problematic” insofar as it is stands for the understanding
“that being is never explicable through beings but is respectively
already the ‘transcendental’ for every entity.”26 There is probably no
passage that better displays Heidegger with one foot firmly in a tradition
and another beyond it. But there is more than one way to interpret
his position here. In a less generous moment, we can interpret it
as mere fence-straddling or we can accept his own interpretation,
namely, that one foot must be planted firmly in a tradition in order
to be able to push off from it and make the leap to a new beginning
with the other.27 In any event, the question presents itself: are the
motives for the transcendental turn from empiricist and naturalistic
thinking no longer at work in the new, allegedly postmetaphysical and
posttranscendental beginning which Heidegger is attempting to prepare
for?
36
2. Heidegger’s Criticisms of Transcendentalism
One key text signaling Heidegger’s repudiation of the notion of transcendence
and the transcendental philosophy entailed by it is to be
found towards the conclusion of Part Three, “The Pass” (Das Zuspiel)
of the Beiträge. It is understandable that the critical discussion is to be
found here, since the pass is meant to prepare the way for another
beginning to thinking, precisely through an indispensable, detached,
yet thoughtful exchange with the thinkers who define the history of
the first beginning.28 Precisely in this pass, the task of thinking is to
appropriate the first beginning in an original way, a way that is concealed
from those thinkers themselves and allows us, indeed, even compels
us to set foot in another (but presumably not opposite) beginning.29
This transpires, Heidegger maintains, in a transition from the guiding
or leading question (what is the entity?) to the basic or ground question (what
is being? what is its truth?) or, as he also puts it, from thinking precipitated—
Vorgriff —by human beings (in the form of the correctness of
assertions and the objectivity of objects) to thinking that grounds being
human and completely transforms our relations to beings.30
Since the
leading question is the definitive question of metaphysics, the pass
amounts to overturning or, better, twisting free of metaphysics, a way
of thinking that “scales over beings to beingness (idea).”31 Here, without
explicitly invoking the term ‘transcendence’, Heidegger identifies
the inherently transcendent character of metaphysics, the sort of philosophy
that makes up the history of thinking from its first inception.
Heidegger locates his “historical” lectures in the ambit of the task
of the pass. In this context he provides an important clue to his assessment
of his own transcendental moves. He speaks of retracing Kant’s
major steps “and yet overturning the ‘transcendental’ departure point
by means of Da-sein.”
In the same brief section (§88) he adds that
this was one path, among others, for showing that being, in order to
prevail, requires the grounding of its truth, a grounding necessarily consummated
as Da-sein, by means of which all idealism and metaphysics
in general are overcome. Yet he ends by remarking that this effort,
as “a necessary unfolding of the first beginning,” first stumbled into
the dark, with the result that it is only from the standpoint of the
other beginning that it can be conceived.32 In this way Heidegger characterizes
his work in the late 1920s: though it falls short because of
its heritage, it has the unmistakably “twofold transitional character of
at once conceiving metaphysics more originally and thereby overturning
it.” The fact that it points the way to a question that cannot be posed
by metaphysics and hence requires another beginning explains the
torso of fundamental ontology—and perhaps some of Heidegger’s reasons
for destroying the unpublished remainder of Sein und Zeit.33
It is in the context of sketching the pervasive influence of the Platonic
understanding of fid°a upon Western metaphysics that Heidegger provides
perhaps his most revealing account of philosophies centering on a
notion of transcendence, including his own earlier “transcendental”
efforts. The immediate context is one of the concluding and lengthier
sections of Part Three, namely, the section entitled “The fid°a, Platonism
and Idealism.” Heidegger begins this section by recounting how fid°a—
initially understood as the unifying look something presents as a constant,
available presence and presents to a potential onlooker (and
ultimately, perceiver or thinker)—came to be identified with the beingness
of beings. Heidegger acknowledges, to be sure, that Plato’s awareness
of being as something more, requiring a move beyond this beingness
(§p°keina t∞w oEsiaw), effectively brings the leading question of metaphysics
up against its limits. But because his questioning is only directed
at beings and their beingness, he can only determine that dimension
beyond beings in terms of what characterizes beingness in relation to
human beings, i.e., as something good or suitable to them. “Beingness
[Seiendheit] is not conceived in [a] more primordial way any more,
but instead is evaluated in such a way that the valuation itself is put
forth as the highest point.”34 Heidegger contends, further, that Plato’s
formulation of the leading question of Western metaphysics and his
answer to it provided the framework and paradigm for all subsequent
Western interpretations of being.
After tracing the transformations in the notion of the idea that led
to idealism (the equation of the beingness of beings with their being
presented or represented),35 Heidegger notes how the influential notion
of transcendence emerges from the Platonic interpretation of being.
For Heidegger the core of that Platonic interpretation is once again
the construal of entities in terms of the constant look—the fid°a—that
they present over many different and changing circumstances. So construed,
the beingness of a being is the fid°a or e‰dow that is common
(koinOn) or generic (g°nh).
Insofar as the idea (the beingness of beings)
is put forward as common to, and yet beyond, any particular beings,
its separateness (xvrismOw) from beings is also posited. This manner of
representing being as separate from beings is, Heidegger maintains,
“the origin of ‘transcendence’ in its various forms.”
With this brief introduction, Heidegger then identifies five kinds of
transcendence in the following order: ontic, ontological, fundamental
ontological, epistemological, and metaphysical. . . .”
http://www.bu.edu/philo/files/2013/09/d-heidegger-transcendentalism.pdf
Also helpful, from the SEP article on Metaphysics:
". . . Most current work in the philosophy of mind presupposes physicalism, and it is generally agreed that a physicalistic theory that does not simply deny the reality of the mental (that is not an “eliminativist” theory), raises metaphysical questions. Such a theory must, of course, find a place for the mental in a wholly physical world, and such a place exists only if mental events and states are certain special physical events and states. There are at least three important metaphysical questions raised by these theories. First, granted that all particular mental events or states are identical with particular physical events or states, can it also be that some or all mental universals (‘event-types’ and ‘state-types’ are the usual terms) are identical with physical universals? Secondly, does physicalism imply that mental events and states cannot really be causes (does physicalism imply a kind of epiphenomenalism)? Thirdly, can a physical thing have non-physical properties—might it be that mental properties like “thinking of Vienna” or “perceiving redly” are non-physical properties of physical organisms? This last question, of course, raises a more basic metaphysical question, ‘What is a non-physical property?’ And all forms of the identity theory raise fundamental metaphysical questions, ontological questions, questions like, ‘What is an event?’ and ‘What is a state?’.
4. The Methodology of Metaphysics . . . ."
Metaphysics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)