• NEW! LOWEST RATES EVER -- SUPPORT THE SHOW AND ENJOY THE VERY BEST PREMIUM PARACAST EXPERIENCE! Welcome to The Paracast+, eight years young! For a low subscription fee, you can download the ad-free version of The Paracast and the exclusive, member-only, After The Paracast bonus podcast, featuring color commentary, exclusive interviews, the continuation of interviews that began on the main episode of The Paracast. We also offer lifetime memberships! Flash! Take advantage of our lowest rates ever! Act now! It's easier than ever to susbcribe! You can sign up right here!

    Subscribe to The Paracast Newsletter!

Consciousness and the Paranormal — Part 3

Free episodes:

Status
Not open for further replies.
Soupie, I think I've come across a philosopher or two that might be to your taste. Start with this blog and give it a try:

[URL='https://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/']Larval Subjects . .[/URL]
https://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2015/02/12/pan-ecologism/#more-7835

This looks like a tender place to tuck in:

[url="https://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2010/01/12/object-oriented-ontology-a-manifesto-part-i/"]Onticology– A Manifesto for Object-Oriented Ontology Part I | Larval Subjects .


I read his bit about slime molds in the "about" section and the post on onto-cartography ... not sure what to make of it? Is it an objectivication of dasein? A call to engineer our own identity and way of being? How do I approach this? I know I need a lot more background ...

[/URL]
 
Voila. It was you, Steve, who found the online copy of Speculative Realism back in part 2, in October of last year:

Consciousness and the Paranormal — Part 2 | Page 81 | The Paracast Community Forums


Not exactly. The online book of the same title still needs to be linked, but what you provided in your link to the 'Speculative Realism Pathfinder" is a summary of the whole schmear of OOO and associated thinking. Very useful, very detailed.
 
from Part 2:

""E. Terms
Speculative Realism is generally considered “a useful umbrella term, chosen precisely because it was vague enough to encompass a variety of fundamentally heterogeneous philosophical research programmes.” (Brassier, 2009) These philosophies, while at once radically different from one another, could be said to find some coherence in their opposition to correlationist philosophies; to quote Ray Brassier again, “the only thing that unites us is antipathy to what Quentin Meillassoux calls ‘correlationism’—the doctrine, especially prevalent among ‘Continental’ philosophers, that humans and world cannot be conceived in isolation from one other—a ‘correlationist’ is any philosopher who insists that the human-world correlate is philosophy’s sole legitimate concern” (2009). An analogy could be drawn to the term “postmodernism,” which is used to label a very diverse set of theories which nonetheless could be said to be united in their opposition to the modernist project of enlightenment."

I added at that point: "I think that Quentin Meillassoux is the one I need to read next since he appears to be the philosopher in this group who first reacts against phenomenological philosophy. I'm ready to give up the idea that "the human-world correlate is philosophy’s sole legitimate concern" {and I'm not sure I ever subconsciously subscribed to that idea}, but I want to find out the particulars of his critique of Merleau-Ponty re this basic premise. In my reading of MP, I think this claim must be difficult to support given MP's posthumously published work, especially that published under the title Nature and the insight into the chiasmic relation of subjectivity and objectivity in the previous book The Visible and the Invisible and the key paper "Eye and Mind."
 
from Part 2:

""E. Terms
Speculative Realism is generally considered “a useful umbrella term, chosen precisely because it was vague enough to encompass a variety of fundamentally heterogeneous philosophical research programmes.” (Brassier, 2009) These philosophies, while at once radically different from one another, could be said to find some coherence in their opposition to correlationist philosophies; to quote Ray Brassier again, “the only thing that unites us is antipathy to what Quentin Meillassoux calls ‘correlationism’—the doctrine, especially prevalent among ‘Continental’ philosophers, that humans and world cannot be conceived in isolation from one other—a ‘correlationist’ is any philosopher who insists that the human-world correlate is philosophy’s sole legitimate concern” (2009)."


Both assertions made in the highlighted text are misrepresentations of Continental philosohers in general and phenomenologists in particular.
 
from Part 2:

""E. Terms
Speculative Realism is generally considered “a useful umbrella term, chosen precisely because it was vague enough to encompass a variety of fundamentally heterogeneous philosophical research programmes.” (Brassier, 2009) These philosophies, while at once radically different from one another, could be said to find some coherence in their opposition to correlationist philosophies; to quote Ray Brassier again, “the only thing that unites us is antipathy to what Quentin Meillassoux calls ‘correlationism’—the doctrine, especially prevalent among ‘Continental’ philosophers, that humans and world cannot be conceived in isolation from one other—a ‘correlationist’ is any philosopher who insists that the human-world correlate is philosophy’s sole legitimate concern” (2009). An analogy could be drawn to the term “postmodernism,” which is used to label a very diverse set of theories which nonetheless could be said to be united in their opposition to the modernist project of enlightenment."

I added at that point: "I think that Quentin Meillassoux is the one I need to read next since he appears to be the philosopher in this group who first reacts against phenomenological philosophy. I'm ready to give up the idea that "the human-world correlate is philosophy’s sole legitimate concern" {and I'm not sure I ever subconsciously subscribed to that idea}, but I want to find out the particulars of his critique of Merleau-Ponty re this basic premise. In my reading of MP, I think this claim must be difficult to support given MP's posthumously published work, especially that published under the title Nature and the insight into the chiasmic relation of subjectivity and objectivity in the previous book The Visible and the Invisible and the key paper "Eye and Mind."

I remember you saying that ...
 
Here's 'the one immediately following' the link above, which I want to post in full here:

"More from Brassier

"I am a nihilist because I still believe in truth."

Heroic nihilism ...

notice how he distinguishes his view from the Existentialists:

"All this may sound platitudinous: surely existentialists had already realized this? But the difference is that existentialists thought it was still possible for human consciousness to provide the meaning that was absent from nature: existence may be meaningless, but man’s task is to provide it with a meaning.

My contention is that this solution is no longer credible, because a project is now underway to understand and explain human consciousness in terms that are compatible with the natural sciences, such that the meanings generated by consciousness can themselves be understood and explained as the products of purposeless but perfectly intelligible processes, which are at once neurobiological and sociohistorical.

My claim is not that science has succeeded in explaining consciousness, but only that considerable progress has been made, and that the burden of proof lies with those who insist on denying such progress and who presume to dismiss the attempt as impossible in principle. There have been plenty of such attempts, and doubtless there will be more, but I find none of them remotely persuasive, and neither should those scientists actually engaged in trying to understand and explain the human mind."


Now would be a good time to ask yourself WWND?


What Would Nietzsche Do indeed. He'd do what I do and decide not to waste time on Brassier.
 
And then there's Lacan, of whose writings I am presently still ignorant. We shall also have to deal with him, and ultimately also with Derrida at a minimum. The same open-source site on which you found The Speculative Turn also provides open-source this book Lacan and Philosophy: The New Generation, a collection of papers on Lacan from various disciplinary applications, edited by a scholar who by pure (and kind of amazing) synchronicity was mentioned to me on the telephone an hour ago: Lorenzo Chiesa. Read the opening pages of his editorial introduction to the volume, "Towards a New Philosophical-Psychoanalytic Materialism and Realism," to see if it interests you.

http://re-press.org/book-files/9780992373412_Lacan_and_Philosophy.pdf
 
The following article showed up in my stream, an interview about Radical Embodied Cognition. It's an alternative to a computational, representational theory of mind. Very interesting. However, it appears to me to be even more mechanistic and deterministic than the computational, representational approach to mind.

Radical embodied cognition: an interview with Andrew Wilson « Mind Hacks

The computational approach is the orthodoxy in psychological science. We try and understand the mind using the metaphors of information processing and the storage and retrieval of representations. These ideas are so common that it is easy to forget that there is any alternative. Andrew Wilson is on a mission to remind us that there is an alternative – a radical, non-representational, non-information processing take on what cognition is. ...
At the end of the interview, several books and links were given for further reading about REC.

Notes from Two Scientific Psychologists: What else could it be? The case of the centrifugal govenor.

Previously, I’ve dismissed the idea of mental representation because 1) no one knows what a representation is and 2) the arguments for representation tend to be pretty weak. Now, I’d like to spend a bit of time discussing a possible alternative – a dynamical systems approach to cognition. To frame this discussion, I’m going to summarise a very handy philosophy paper by Van Gelder (1995) in which he distinguishes between a computational and dynamical solution to a particular problem (see also Andrew's post on the polar planimeter). Van Gelder has clearly picked a side - that cognition emerges from dynamical systems and that cognitive processes are evolutions in the state-space within these systems. One of the main arguments for computation is that it’s difficult to imagine what else could be going on (see footnotes p. 346 for references for this argument). So, Van Gelder wrote this paper, not to decisively rule out computation, but to provide an answer to the question “what else could [cognition] be?” ...

However, it is also possible to describe decisions in terms of state space evolution in a dynamical system. For example, motivational oscillatory theory (MOT; cf. Townsend) describes oscillations resulting from satiation of persisting desires. We approach food when we’re hungry, but not when we’ve just eaten and are temporarily satiated. It’s possible to interpret this behaviour as a decision – when I’m hungry, I decide to eat. But, in this model there are no discrete states and no algorithmic processes effecting transformation on these states. There is just the evolution of the system over time. Furthermore, peculiarities in human decisions that cannot be accounted for by utility theory (e.g., the common consequence effect Allais paradox - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia emerge naturally in the dynamic framework.

The ability to describe the governing problem in two completely different ways is a good illustration of the choice facing cognitive psychology. The computer/information processing model is so embedded in most people’s conception of cognition that it can feel impossible to characterise the system any other way. However, Van Gelder outlines a clear and promising, nonrepresentational alternative based on dynamical systems. In the future I’ll tie this discussion back to Gibson and describe why this is the type of solution animals, who have to solve real problems related to survival, are likely to have evolved (see also here).

This is some of the clearest, most concise, jargon-free writing on embodied cognition that I've encountered. It's finally nice to understand what is meant by the idea that "the brain is not a computer." However, this alternative to computation and representation seems to reduce the mind to mere mechanisms that are tightly, intimately, and deterministically linked to the environment.

So I'm wondering if the Embodied Cognition approach to mind leaves any room for free will, and I found the following, also easy to read, collection of essays.

http://www.humanamente.eu/PDF/Issue15_CompletePDF.pdf

Agency: From Embodied Cognition to Free Will

For the phenomenological debate, the notion of embodiment coincides
with the rebuttal of what is usually considered the Cartesian dualism, that is,
the segregation of any bodily influence from the subjective experiential
domain. Crossing the history of western thought, this problem acquires a
critical dimension in the twentieth century philosophical debate. The way to
understand the relationship between body and consciousness finds a new style
after the establishment of the phenomenological framework.
Following the
path originally drawn by Husserl and successively developed by Merleau-Ponty,
it is possible to figure out how the phenomenological tradition, from its early
stages, has originally approached the mind-body problem underlying the
opportunity to develop an interactive conception based on the assumption of a
radical interweaving between the experiential and the bodily domains.

According to this view, perceptive experience can be conceived as a method
through which the subject travels in the environment following his motor
intentions and exploiting his skillful knowledge of the sensorimotor
constraints that link the execution of a goal oriented action to the variation of
the phenomenal features.

Working on the clarification of the notion of embodiment we have the
opportunity to cease to unreflectively privilege only one possible explanation
of our experience. The human mind, observed through the lenses of
embodiment, emerges at the interface of the brain, the body, the material and
social environment. This is an inextricable mash influencing all aspects of our
life. We are agents whose nature is fixed by a complex interaction involving our
personal experience, a particular kind of physical embodiment and a certain
embedding in the environment. This very combination of experience, flesh and
environment is the main character of our being in the world.


The assumption of agency as a critical aspect of our experience motivates
the introduction of another classical philosophical problem such as that
concerning the notion of free will. We usually consider human beings natural
organisms that are morally responsible for their own actions. Yet this
assumption represents one of the most intriguing puzzles that, from ancient
Greece to the contemporary era, has absorbed philosophers and scientists of
every kind. Are we really free agents?
What does our subjective experience of
agency reveal to us? And how do these questions relate to the fact that we are
natural embodied beings?

Except in cases where we are physically constrained, we consider ourselves
free beings that think, believe and act autonomously, that is, according to the
states of consciousness that characterize our own mental life. We consider
ourselves responsible for our own acts because we perceive ourselves as being
able to freely project the actions that our body can perform. Accordingly, the
possibility of a free choice appears to be strictly related to the possibility of
assigning independence to a particular domain such as our subjective
consciousness.

The subjective sense of agency, that is, the feeling that we control our own
movements and actions, is certainly an essential, constant element of our
everyday experience. It seems obvious to us that the casual chain leading to the
execution of an action critically derives from our conscious intention.
However, we can try for a moment to imagine we do not have any real power
over our actions. We can imagine that we are prisoners of an illusion that gives
us the impression that we are the causes of our actions, but that we are actually
nothing but automata governed by a sophisticated system of behavioral laws. If
we carried through with this imaginative effort, then the very meaning of the
word “freedom” would need to be modified according to the idea that those we
perceive as our voluntary actions are, in reality, independent of our will. But
does this make sense? Or is it only a philosophical trick?
 
The following article showed up in my stream, an interview about Radical Embodied Cognition. It's an alternative to a computational, representational theory of mind. Very interesting. However, it appears to me to be even more mechanistic and deterministic than the computational, representational approach to mind.

Radical embodied cognition: an interview with Andrew Wilson « Mind Hacks

The computational approach is the orthodoxy in psychological science. We try and understand the mind using the metaphors of information processing and the storage and retrieval of representations. These ideas are so common that it is easy to forget that there is any alternative. Andrew Wilson is on a mission to remind us that there is an alternative – a radical, non-representational, non-information processing take on what cognition is. ...
At the end of the interview, several books and links were given for further reading about REC.

Notes from Two Scientific Psychologists: What else could it be? The case of the centrifugal govenor.

Previously, I’ve dismissed the idea of mental representation because 1) no one knows what a representation is and 2) the arguments for representation tend to be pretty weak. Now, I’d like to spend a bit of time discussing a possible alternative – a dynamical systems approach to cognition. To frame this discussion, I’m going to summarise a very handy philosophy paper by Van Gelder (1995) in which he distinguishes between a computational and dynamical solution to a particular problem (see also Andrew's post on the polar planimeter). Van Gelder has clearly picked a side - that cognition emerges from dynamical systems and that cognitive processes are evolutions in the state-space within these systems. One of the main arguments for computation is that it’s difficult to imagine what else could be going on (see footnotes p. 346 for references for this argument). So, Van Gelder wrote this paper, not to decisively rule out computation, but to provide an answer to the question “what else could [cognition] be?” ...

However, it is also possible to describe decisions in terms of state space evolution in a dynamical system. For example, motivational oscillatory theory (MOT; cf. Townsend) describes oscillations resulting from satiation of persisting desires. We approach food when we’re hungry, but not when we’ve just eaten and are temporarily satiated. It’s possible to interpret this behaviour as a decision – when I’m hungry, I decide to eat. But, in this model there are no discrete states and no algorithmic processes effecting transformation on these states. There is just the evolution of the system over time. Furthermore, peculiarities in human decisions that cannot be accounted for by utility theory (e.g., the common consequence effect Allais paradox - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia emerge naturally in the dynamic framework.

The ability to describe the governing problem in two completely different ways is a good illustration of the choice facing cognitive psychology. The computer/information processing model is so embedded in most people’s conception of cognition that it can feel impossible to characterise the system any other way. However, Van Gelder outlines a clear and promising, nonrepresentational alternative based on dynamical systems. In the future I’ll tie this discussion back to Gibson and describe why this is the type of solution animals, who have to solve real problems related to survival, are likely to have evolved (see also here).

This is some of the clearest, most concise, jargon-free writing on embodied cognition that I've encountered. It's finally nice to understand what is meant by the idea that "the brain is not a computer." However, this alternative to computation and representation seems to reduce the mind to mere mechanisms that are tightly, intimately, and deterministically linked to the environment.

So I'm wondering if the Embodied Cognition approach to mind leaves any room for free will, and I found the following, also easy to read, collection of essays.

http://www.humanamente.eu/PDF/Issue15_CompletePDF.pdf

Agency: From Embodied Cognition to Free Will

For the phenomenological debate, the notion of embodiment coincides
with the rebuttal of what is usually considered the Cartesian dualism, that is,
the segregation of any bodily influence from the subjective experiential
domain. Crossing the history of western thought, this problem acquires a
critical dimension in the twentieth century philosophical debate. The way to
understand the relationship between body and consciousness finds a new style
after the establishment of the phenomenological framework.
Following the
path originally drawn by Husserl and successively developed by Merleau-Ponty,
it is possible to figure out how the phenomenological tradition, from its early
stages, has originally approached the mind-body problem underlying the
opportunity to develop an interactive conception based on the assumption of a
radical interweaving between the experiential and the bodily domains.

According to this view, perceptive experience can be conceived as a method
through which the subject travels in the environment following his motor
intentions and exploiting his skillful knowledge of the sensorimotor
constraints that link the execution of a goal oriented action to the variation of
the phenomenal features.

Working on the clarification of the notion of embodiment we have the
opportunity to cease to unreflectively privilege only one possible explanation
of our experience. The human mind, observed through the lenses of
embodiment, emerges at the interface of the brain, the body, the material and
social environment. This is an inextricable mash influencing all aspects of our
life. We are agents whose nature is fixed by a complex interaction involving our
personal experience, a particular kind of physical embodiment and a certain
embedding in the environment. This very combination of experience, flesh and
environment is the main character of our being in the world.


The assumption of agency as a critical aspect of our experience motivates
the introduction of another classical philosophical problem such as that
concerning the notion of free will. We usually consider human beings natural
organisms that are morally responsible for their own actions. Yet this
assumption represents one of the most intriguing puzzles that, from ancient
Greece to the contemporary era, has absorbed philosophers and scientists of
every kind. Are we really free agents?
What does our subjective experience of
agency reveal to us? And how do these questions relate to the fact that we are
natural embodied beings?

Except in cases where we are physically constrained, we consider ourselves
free beings that think, believe and act autonomously, that is, according to the
states of consciousness that characterize our own mental life. We consider
ourselves responsible for our own acts because we perceive ourselves as being
able to freely project the actions that our body can perform. Accordingly, the
possibility of a free choice appears to be strictly related to the possibility of
assigning independence to a particular domain such as our subjective
consciousness.

The subjective sense of agency, that is, the feeling that we control our own
movements and actions, is certainly an essential, constant element of our
everyday experience. It seems obvious to us that the casual chain leading to the
execution of an action critically derives from our conscious intention.
However, we can try for a moment to imagine we do not have any real power
over our actions. We can imagine that we are prisoners of an illusion that gives
us the impression that we are the causes of our actions, but that we are actually
nothing but automata governed by a sophisticated system of behavioral laws. If
we carried through with this imaginative effort, then the very meaning of the
word “freedom” would need to be modified according to the idea that those we
perceive as our voluntary actions are, in reality, independent of our will. But
does this make sense? Or is it only a philosophical trick?

It's funny to say you can imagine that you have no free will ... it's kind of like saying you choose not to have free will ... does it make sense to say you have a choice? is their free will about free will? if you had free will, could you give it up?

some people do seem to do something like this - giving their will to a (G)g-d or to the state or the millitary or a "beloved" or some cause ... or to an illness or depression (I'm not discounting the effects of depression - but we do say some things rob of us of our will) do the mindless baby lonians fit in here somewhere? What's the natural history of free will?
 
Here's 'the one immediately following' the link above, which I want to post in full here:




What Would Nietzsche Do indeed. He'd do what I do and decide not to waste time on Brassier.

And in this corner ... a philosophical lightweight, Rrrrray ah "boom boom" Brassier!

And in the red corner, rrrrrrockin' it with an umlaut from Rocken ... weighing in at an inestimable gravity, one of the all time heavyweights of world philosophy ... the Pugnacious Prussian Pugilist ...

Friedrich ... Wilhelm ... von Nnnnnnietzsche!

the crowd goes wild

It's Nietzsche by a KO 11 seconds in to the first round.

Nietzscheil_570xN.jpg
 
Last edited by a moderator:
The following article showed up in my stream, an interview about Radical Embodied Cognition. It's an alternative to a computational, representational theory of mind. Very interesting. However, it appears to me to be even more mechanistic and deterministic than the computational, representational approach to mind.

Radical embodied cognition: an interview with Andrew Wilson « Mind Hacks

The computational approach is the orthodoxy in psychological science. We try and understand the mind using the metaphors of information processing and the storage and retrieval of representations. These ideas are so common that it is easy to forget that there is any alternative. Andrew Wilson is on a mission to remind us that there is an alternative – a radical, non-representational, non-information processing take on what cognition is. ...
At the end of the interview, several books and links were given for further reading about REC.

Notes from Two Scientific Psychologists: What else could it be? The case of the centrifugal govenor.

Previously, I’ve dismissed the idea of mental representation because 1) no one knows what a representation is and 2) the arguments for representation tend to be pretty weak. Now, I’d like to spend a bit of time discussing a possible alternative – a dynamical systems approach to cognition. To frame this discussion, I’m going to summarise a very handy philosophy paper by Van Gelder (1995) in which he distinguishes between a computational and dynamical solution to a particular problem (see also Andrew's post on the polar planimeter). Van Gelder has clearly picked a side - that cognition emerges from dynamical systems and that cognitive processes are evolutions in the state-space within these systems. One of the main arguments for computation is that it’s difficult to imagine what else could be going on (see footnotes p. 346 for references for this argument). So, Van Gelder wrote this paper, not to decisively rule out computation, but to provide an answer to the question “what else could [cognition] be?” ...

However, it is also possible to describe decisions in terms of state space evolution in a dynamical system. For example, motivational oscillatory theory (MOT; cf. Townsend) describes oscillations resulting from satiation of persisting desires. We approach food when we’re hungry, but not when we’ve just eaten and are temporarily satiated. It’s possible to interpret this behaviour as a decision – when I’m hungry, I decide to eat. But, in this model there are no discrete states and no algorithmic processes effecting transformation on these states. There is just the evolution of the system over time. Furthermore, peculiarities in human decisions that cannot be accounted for by utility theory (e.g., the common consequence effect Allais paradox - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia emerge naturally in the dynamic framework.

The ability to describe the governing problem in two completely different ways is a good illustration of the choice facing cognitive psychology. The computer/information processing model is so embedded in most people’s conception of cognition that it can feel impossible to characterise the system any other way. However, Van Gelder outlines a clear and promising, nonrepresentational alternative based on dynamical systems. In the future I’ll tie this discussion back to Gibson and describe why this is the type of solution animals, who have to solve real problems related to survival, are likely to have evolved (see also here).

This is some of the clearest, most concise, jargon-free writing on embodied cognition that I've encountered. It's finally nice to understand what is meant by the idea that "the brain is not a computer." However, this alternative to computation and representation seems to reduce the mind to mere mechanisms that are tightly, intimately, and deterministically linked to the environment.

So I'm wondering if the Embodied Cognition approach to mind leaves any room for free will, and I found the following, also easy to read, collection of essays.

http://www.humanamente.eu/PDF/Issue15_CompletePDF.pdf

Agency: From Embodied Cognition to Free Will

For the phenomenological debate, the notion of embodiment coincides
with the rebuttal of what is usually considered the Cartesian dualism, that is,
the segregation of any bodily influence from the subjective experiential
domain. Crossing the history of western thought, this problem acquires a
critical dimension in the twentieth century philosophical debate. The way to
understand the relationship between body and consciousness finds a new style
after the establishment of the phenomenological framework.
Following the
path originally drawn by Husserl and successively developed by Merleau-Ponty,
it is possible to figure out how the phenomenological tradition, from its early
stages, has originally approached the mind-body problem underlying the
opportunity to develop an interactive conception based on the assumption of a
radical interweaving between the experiential and the bodily domains.

According to this view, perceptive experience can be conceived as a method
through which the subject travels in the environment following his motor
intentions and exploiting his skillful knowledge of the sensorimotor
constraints that link the execution of a goal oriented action to the variation of
the phenomenal features.

Working on the clarification of the notion of embodiment we have the
opportunity to cease to unreflectively privilege only one possible explanation
of our experience. The human mind, observed through the lenses of
embodiment, emerges at the interface of the brain, the body, the material and
social environment. This is an inextricable mash influencing all aspects of our
life. We are agents whose nature is fixed by a complex interaction involving our
personal experience, a particular kind of physical embodiment and a certain
embedding in the environment. This very combination of experience, flesh and
environment is the main character of our being in the world.


The assumption of agency as a critical aspect of our experience motivates
the introduction of another classical philosophical problem such as that
concerning the notion of free will. We usually consider human beings natural
organisms that are morally responsible for their own actions. Yet this
assumption represents one of the most intriguing puzzles that, from ancient
Greece to the contemporary era, has absorbed philosophers and scientists of
every kind. Are we really free agents?
What does our subjective experience of
agency reveal to us? And how do these questions relate to the fact that we are
natural embodied beings?

Except in cases where we are physically constrained, we consider ourselves
free beings that think, believe and act autonomously, that is, according to the
states of consciousness that characterize our own mental life. We consider
ourselves responsible for our own acts because we perceive ourselves as being
able to freely project the actions that our body can perform. Accordingly, the
possibility of a free choice appears to be strictly related to the possibility of
assigning independence to a particular domain such as our subjective
consciousness.

The subjective sense of agency, that is, the feeling that we control our own
movements and actions, is certainly an essential, constant element of our
everyday experience. It seems obvious to us that the casual chain leading to the
execution of an action critically derives from our conscious intention.
However, we can try for a moment to imagine we do not have any real power
over our actions. We can imagine that we are prisoners of an illusion that gives
us the impression that we are the causes of our actions, but that we are actually
nothing but automata governed by a sophisticated system of behavioral laws. If
we carried through with this imaginative effort, then the very meaning of the
word “freedom” would need to be modified according to the idea that those we
perceive as our voluntary actions are, in reality, independent of our will. But
does this make sense? Or is it only a philosophical trick?

Excellent work pulling all that together, Soupie. And thank you for the links, which I'm about to follow today.
 
Last edited:
Status
Not open for further replies.
Back
Top